relevance condition
Recently Published Documents


TOTAL DOCUMENTS

7
(FIVE YEARS 1)

H-INDEX

1
(FIVE YEARS 0)

2022 ◽  
Vol 16 (4) ◽  
pp. 1-20
Author(s):  
Junkun Yuan ◽  
Anpeng Wu ◽  
Kun Kuang ◽  
Bo Li ◽  
Runze Wu ◽  
...  

Instrumental variables (IVs), sources of treatment randomization that are conditionally independent of the outcome, play an important role in causal inference with unobserved confounders. However, the existing IV-based counterfactual prediction methods need well-predefined IVs, while it’s an art rather than science to find valid IVs in many real-world scenes. Moreover, the predefined hand-made IVs could be weak or erroneous by violating the conditions of valid IVs. These thorny facts hinder the application of the IV-based counterfactual prediction methods. In this article, we propose a novel Automatic Instrumental Variable decomposition (AutoIV) algorithm to automatically generate representations serving the role of IVs from observed variables (IV candidates). Specifically, we let the learned IV representations satisfy the relevance condition with the treatment and exclusion condition with the outcome via mutual information maximization and minimization constraints, respectively. We also learn confounder representations by encouraging them to be relevant to both the treatment and the outcome. The IV and confounder representations compete for the information with their constraints in an adversarial game, which allows us to get valid IV representations for IV-based counterfactual prediction. Extensive experiments demonstrate that our method generates valid IV representations for accurate IV-based counterfactual prediction.


Author(s):  
Stephen Read

‘Relevance logic’ came into being in the late 1950s, inspired by Wilhelm Ackermann, who rejected certain formulas of the form A→B on the grounds that ‘the truth of A has nothing to do with the question whether there is a logical connection between B and A’. The central idea of relevance logic is to give an account of logical consequence, or entailment, for which a connection of relevance between premises and conclusion is a necessary condition. In both classical and intuitionistic logic, this condition is missing, as is highlighted by the validity in those logics of the ‘spread law’, A &∼A→B; a contradiction ‘spreads’ to every proposition, and simple inconsistency is equivalent to absolute inconsistency. In relevance logic the spread law fails, and the simple inconsistency of a theory (that a set of formulas entails a contradiction) is distinguished from absolute inconsistency (or triviality: that a set of formulas entails every proposition). The programme of relevance logic is to characterize a logic, or a range of logics, satisfying the relevance condition, and to study theories based on such logics, such as relevant arithmetic and relevant set theory.


Author(s):  
Neil Tennant

Ironically Anderson and Belnap argue for the rejection of Disjunctive Syllogism by means of an argument that appears to employ it. We aim to establish a ‘variable-sharing’ result for Classical Core Logic that is stronger than any such result for any other system. We define an exigent relevance condition R(X,A) on the premise-set X and the conclusion A of any proof, exploiting positive and negative occurrences of subformulae. This treatment includes first-order proofs. Our main result on relevance is that for every proof of A from X in Classical Core Logic, we have R(X,A). R(X,A) is a best possible explication of the sought notion of relevance. Our result is optimal, and challenges relevantists in the Anderson–Belnap tradition to identify any strengthening of the relation R(X,A) that can be shown to hold for some subsystem of Anderson–Belnap R but that can be shown to fail for Classical Core Logic.


2009 ◽  
Vol 104 (2) ◽  
pp. 500-508 ◽  
Author(s):  
Wen-Bin Chiou ◽  
Ming-Hsu Chang ◽  
Chien-Lung Chen

Raghunathan and Pham conducted a pioneer study in 1999 on the motivational influences of anxiety and sadness on decision making and indicated that anxiety would motivate individuals to be risk averse, whereas sadness would motivate individuals to be risk taking. A replication study was employed in the domain of perceived travel risk. Compared to participants in a neutral mood, anxious participants showed higher perceived travel risk than sad participants. Moreover, the differential effect of anxiety and sadness on perceived travel risk was only pronounced under the high personal relevance condition, in which participants made personal decisions and expected that they would be affected by the outcomes. In general, the results extend the notion proposed by Raghunathan and Pham suggesting that travelers' implicit goals primed by anxiety or sadness used for mood-repair purposes appear to be moderated by personal relevance.


1989 ◽  
Vol 21 (04) ◽  
pp. 930-932
Author(s):  
Emad El-Neweihi ◽  
Fan C. Meng

A conjecture due to Block et al. (1989), concerning the number of critical connection vectors to the various performance levels of a discrete L-superadditive structure function, is proved. When the components of the discrete L-superadditive structure function are further assumed to satisfy a certain relevance condition due to Griffith (1980), it is shown that there is exactly one critical connection vector to each performance level.


1989 ◽  
Vol 21 (4) ◽  
pp. 930-932 ◽  
Author(s):  
Emad El-Neweihi ◽  
Fan C. Meng

A conjecture due to Block et al. (1989), concerning the number of critical connection vectors to the various performance levels of a discrete L-superadditive structure function, is proved. When the components of the discrete L-superadditive structure function are further assumed to satisfy a certain relevance condition due to Griffith (1980), it is shown that there is exactly one critical connection vector to each performance level.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document