Washington University Review of Philosophy
Latest Publications


TOTAL DOCUMENTS

11
(FIVE YEARS 11)

H-INDEX

0
(FIVE YEARS 0)

Published By Philosophy Documentation Center

2766-4473

2021 ◽  
Vol 1 ◽  
pp. 34-40
Author(s):  
Tom Cochrane ◽  
Rohan Srivastava ◽  
Alexandra Crotty ◽  


2021 ◽  
Vol 1 ◽  
pp. 53-60
Author(s):  
Thomas Leddy ◽  

Clive Bell’s Art, published in 1913, is widely seen as a founding document in contemporary aesthetics. Yet his formalism and his attendant definition of art as “significant form” is widely rejected in contemporary art discourse and in the philosophy of art. In this paper I argue for a reconsideration of his thought in connection with current discussions of “the aesthetics of everyday life.” Although some, notably Allen Carlson, have argued against application of Bell’s formalism to the aesthetics of everyday life, I claim that this is based on an interpretation of the concept that is overly narrow. First, Li Zehou offers an interpretation of “significant form” that allows in sedimented social meaning. Second, Bell himself offers a more complex theory of significant form by way of his “metaphysical hypothesis,” one that stresses perception of significant form outside the realm of art (for example in nature or in everyday life). Bell’s idea that the artist can perceive significant form in nature allows for significant form to not just be the surface-level formal properties of things. It stresses depth, although a different kind than the cognitive scientific depth Carlson wants. This is a depth that is consistent with the anti-dualism of Spinoza, Marx and Dewey. Reinterpreting Bell in this direction, we can say we are moved by certain relations of lines and colors because they direct our minds to the hidden aspect of things, the spiritual side of the material world referred to by Spinoza and developed by Dewey in his concept of experience. Bell hardly “reduces the everyday to a shadow of itself,” as Carlson puts it, since the everyday, as experienced by the artist or the aesthetically astute observer, has, or potentially has, deep meaning. If we reject Bell’s dualism and his downgrading of sensuous experience, we can rework his idea of pure form to refer to an aspect of things detached, yes, from practical use, but not from particularity or sedimented meaning, not purified of all associations.


2021 ◽  
Vol 1 ◽  
pp. 2-3
Author(s):  
Nathan Hirscher ◽  
Rohan Srivastava ◽  


2021 ◽  
Vol 1 ◽  
pp. 89-93
Author(s):  
Anna Christina Ribeiro ◽  
Ethan Harris ◽  


2021 ◽  
Vol 1 ◽  
pp. 19-25
Author(s):  
Paul C. Taylor ◽  
Ethan Harris ◽  


2021 ◽  
Vol 1 ◽  
pp. 61-65
Author(s):  
Elizabeth Millán Brusslan ◽  
Lauren Bush ◽  
Ethan Harris ◽  


2021 ◽  
Vol 1 ◽  
pp. 26-33
Author(s):  
Frank Boardman ◽  
Keyword(s):  

Certain artworks are––whatever else they are––statements about the value of art. A particularly striking form of such a statement is made by a class of artworks we can call “high-cost art.” High-cost artworks are those with greater costs relative to benefits for their artists or displayers. I will argue here that those art forms that are most likely to include high-cost works are particularly effective at communicating artistic value-claims, and suggest that by so championing the value of art, these artworks themselves increase in artistic value.


2021 ◽  
Vol 1 ◽  
pp. 41-52
Author(s):  
Andrea Lorenzo Baldini ◽  
Nathan Hirscher ◽  


2021 ◽  
Vol 1 ◽  
pp. 1-18
Author(s):  
Katherine Tullmann ◽  

This paper analyzes aesthetic courage, a virtue directed towards aesthetic objects when subjects are asked to confront content that is psychologically or socially risky. I examine aesthetic courage to explore how it plays a role in a virtue theoretic account of the good life. I contend that the virtue theoretic concept of phronesis, or practical wisdom, plays a strong role in guiding the virtuous agent to make decisions about the course of action that promotes her good life. The concept of phronesis in service of the good life acts as the foundation for my concept of aesthetic courage. I analyze several examples of aesthetic courage, including the controversy surrounding the contemplative garden at Stanford University in honor of Chanel Miller and other survivors of sexual assault.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document