Maximal or Greatest Homomorphic Images of Given Type

1968 ◽  
Vol 20 ◽  
pp. 264-271 ◽  
Author(s):  
Takayuki Tamura

Let Q be a quasi-ordered set with respect to ⩽ ; that is, the order ⩽ is reflexive and transitive. An element a of Q is called maximal (minimal) ifa is called greatest (smallest) ifObviously a greatest (smallest) element is maximal (minimal). A greatest (smallest) element in a partially ordered set is unique, but it is not necessarily unique in a quasi-ordered set.

1970 ◽  
Vol 13 (1) ◽  
pp. 115-118 ◽  
Author(s):  
G. Bruns ◽  
H. Lakser

A (meet-) semilattice is an algebra with one binary operation ∧, which is associative, commutative and idempotent. Throughout this paper we are working in the category of semilattices. All categorical or general algebraic notions are to be understood in this category. In every semilattice S the relationdefines a partial ordering of S. The symbol "∨" denotes least upper bounds under this partial ordering. If it is not clear from the context in which partially ordered set a least upper bound is taken, we add this set as an index to the symbol; for example, ∨AX denotes the least upper bound of X in the partially ordered set A.


1957 ◽  
Vol 9 ◽  
pp. 578-582 ◽  
Author(s):  
L. E. Ward

Let (X, ≤) be a partially ordered set, that is, X is a set and ≤ is a reflexive, anti-symmetric, transitive, binary relation on X.We write,for each x ∈ X. If, moreover,exists for each x and y in X, then (X, ≤) is said to be a semi-lattice.


1993 ◽  
Vol 58 (2) ◽  
pp. 435-455 ◽  
Author(s):  
S. Shelah ◽  
D. H. Fremlin

In a series of papers culminating in [9], M. Talagrand, the second author, and others investigated at length the properties and structure of pointwise compact sets of measurable functions. A number of problems, interesting in themselves and important for the theory of Pettis integration, were solved subject to various special axioms. It was left unclear just how far the special axioms were necessary. In particular, several results depended on the fact that it is consistent to suppose that every countable relatively pointwise compact set of Lebesgue measurable functions is ‘stable’ in Talagrand's sense, the point being that stable sets are known to have a variety of properties not shared by all pointwise compact sets. In the present paper we present a model of set theory in which there is a countable relatively pointwise compact set of Lebesgue measurable functions which is not stable and discuss the significance of this model in relation to the original questions. A feature of our model which may be of independent interest is the following: in it, there is a closed negligible set Q ⊆ [0, 1]2 such that whenever D ⊆ [0,1] has outer measure 1, thenhas inner measure 1 (see 2G below).We embark immediately on the central ideas of this paper, setting out a construction of a partially ordered set which forces a fairly technical proposition in measure theory (IS below); the relevance of this proposition to pointwise compact sets will be discussed in §2.


1985 ◽  
Vol 50 (2) ◽  
pp. 502-509
Author(s):  
Marco Forti ◽  
Furio Honsell

T. Jech [4] and M. Takahashi [7] proved that given any partial ordering R in a model of ZFC there is a symmetric submodel of a generic extension of where R is isomorphic to the injective ordering on a set of cardinals.The authors raised the question whether the injective ordering of cardinals can be universal, i.e. whether the following axiom of “cardinal universality” is consistent:CU. For any partially ordered set (X, ≼) there is a bijection f:X → Y such that(i.e. x ≼ y iff ∃g: f(x) → f(y) injective). (See [1].)The consistency of CU relative to ZF0 (Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory without foundation) is proved in [2], but the transfer method of Jech-Sochor-Pincus cannot be applied to obtain consistency with full ZF (including foundation), since CU apparently is not boundable.In this paper the authors define a model of ZF + CU as a symmetric submodel of a generic extension obtained by forcing “à la Easton” with a class of conditions which add κ generic subsets to any regular cardinal κ of a ground model satisfying ZF + V = L.


2016 ◽  
Vol 81 (1) ◽  
pp. 181-200 ◽  
Author(s):  
PAUL GARTSIDE ◽  
ANA MAMATELASHVILI

AbstractOne partially ordered set, Q, is a Tukey quotient of another, P, if there is a map (a Tukey quotient) $\phi :P \to Q$ carrying cofinal sets of P to cofinal sets of Q. Two partial orders which are mutual Tukey quotients of each other are said to be Tukey equivalent. Let ${\cal D}_{\rm{}} $ be the partially ordered set of Tukey equivalence classes of directed sets of size $ \le {\rm{}}$. It is shown that ${\cal D}_{\rm{}} $ contains an antichain of size $2^{\rm{}} $, and so has size $2^{\rm{}} $. The elements of the antichain are of the form ${\cal K}\left( M \right)$, the set of compact subsets of a separable metrizable space M, ordered by inclusion. The order structure of such ${\cal K}\left( M \right)$’s under Tukey quotients is investigated. Relative Tukey quotients are introduced. Applications are given to function spaces and to the complexity of weakly countably determined Banach spaces and Gul’ko compacta.


1969 ◽  
Vol 9 (3-4) ◽  
pp. 361-362
Author(s):  
Vladimir Devidé

Let (S, ≦) be a (non-void) partially ordered set with the property that for every (non-void) chain C (i.e., every totally ordered subset) of S, there exists in S the element sup C. Let SM be the set of all maximal elements s of S. ƒ:S/SM→S be a slowly increasing mapping in the sense that


1984 ◽  
Vol 25 (1) ◽  
pp. 31-33 ◽  
Author(s):  
Hazel Perfect

Throughout, (X, ≤ ) denotes a partially ordered set (p. o. set), where X is assumed to be finite. A subset Y of X is called a k-union if Y contains no chain of length K + 1. In particular, therefore, a 1-union is just an antichain; and it is readily seen that Y is a k-union if and only if it is a union of K antichains. (Dually, a subset Z of X is a k-counion if Z contains no antichain of length k + 1.) We denote by dk (X) the maximum cardinality of a k-union in X, with a similar notation for other p. o. sets. Now let be any partition of X into chains, and write.


2016 ◽  
Vol 81 (1) ◽  
pp. 384-394 ◽  
Author(s):  
ELEFTHERIOS TACHTSIS

AbstractRamsey’s Theorem is naturally connected to the statement “every infinite partially ordered set has either an infinite chain or an infinite anti-chain”. Indeed, it is a well-known result that Ramsey’s Theorem implies the latter principle.In the book “Consequences of the Axiom of Choice” by P. Howard and J. E. Rubin, it is stated as unknown whether the above implication is reversible, that is whether the principle “every infinite partially ordered set has either an infinite chain or an infinite anti-chain” implies Ramsey’s Theorem. The purpose of this paper is to settle the aforementioned open problem. In particular, we construct a suitable Fraenkel–Mostowski permutation model ${\cal N}$ for ZFA and prove that the above principle for infinite partially ordered sets is true in ${\cal N}$, whereas Ramsey’s Theorem is false in ${\cal N}$. Then, based on the existence of ${\cal N}$ and on results of D. Pincus, we show that there is a model of ZF which satisfies “every infinite partially ordered set has either an infinite chain or an infinite anti-chain” and the negation of Ramsey’s Theorem.In addition, we prove that Ramsey’s Theorem (hence, the above principle for infinite partially ordered sets) is true in Mostowski’s linearly ordered model, filling the gap of information in the book “Consequences of the Axiom of Choice”.


1978 ◽  
Vol 19 (1) ◽  
pp. 1-12 ◽  
Author(s):  
D. B. McAlister

An inverse semigroup is called E-unitary if the equations ea = e = e2 together imply a2 = a. In a previous paper [4], the author showed that any E-unitary inverse semigroup is isomorphic to a semigroup constructed from a triple (G, ℋ, ) consisting of a down-directed partially ordered set ℋ, an ideal and subsemilattice of ℋ and a group G acting on ℋ, on the left, by order automorphisms in such a way that ℋ = G. This semigroup is denoted by P(G, ℋ, ); it consists of all pairs (a, g)∈ × G such that g−1a ∈ , under the multiplication


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document