A Partial Look at Trope Theory

Author(s):  
Bo R. Meinertsen
Keyword(s):  
2015 ◽  
Vol 1 (4) ◽  
pp. 635-652 ◽  
Author(s):  
ROBERT K. GARCIA
Keyword(s):  

ABSTRACT:Trope theory is an increasingly prominent contender in contemporary debates about the existence and nature of properties. But it suffers from ambiguity concerning the nature of a trope. Disambiguation reveals two fundamentally different concepts of a trope: modifier tropes and module tropes. These types of tropes are unequally suited for metaphysical work. Modifier tropes have advantages concerning powers, relations, and fundamental determinables, whereas module tropes have advantages concerning perception, causation, character-grounding, and the ontology of substance. Thus, the choice between modifier tropes and module tropes is significant and divides the advantages of trope theorysimpliciter. In addition, each resulting trope theory is unstable: modifier trope theory threatens to collapse into realism, and module trope theory threatens to collapse into austere nominalism. This invites reflection on the stability of trope theory in general.


2021 ◽  
pp. 138-172
Author(s):  
Joseph Mendola

This chapter is a critical discussion of nominalist accounts of the ontology of the basic properties and relations present in our experience. Predicate nominalism, concept nominalism, class nominalism, resemblance nominalism, and trope theory are discussed. Several novel objections to forms of nominalism and trope theory, in other words to accounts of properties that deny they are universals, are developed. These include a series of objections that such accounts are not able to plausibly account for the essential features of specific basic properties that appear in our experience, such as colors, in other words that they misrepresent the modal structure of those properties.


Author(s):  
R. Scott Smith

William Lane Craig has defended nominalism as a kind of “anti–Platonism.” To him, Platonism is inimical to God’s aseity. More recently, he also has defended the penal substitution of Christ. However, he has not brought the two subjects into dialogue with each other. In this essay, I will attempt to do that by exploring the implications of two major types of nominalism, austere nominalism and trope theory, for the penal substitution. I will argue that nominalism will undermine the penal substitution of Christ. Instead, to try to preserve both his anti–Platonism and the penal substitution, a better alternative for Craig is to embrace E. J. Lowe’s immanent universals.


Author(s):  
Jani Hakkarainen ◽  
Markku Keinänen
Keyword(s):  

Synthese ◽  
2009 ◽  
Vol 175 (3) ◽  
pp. 311-326 ◽  
Author(s):  
Anna-Sofia Maurin
Keyword(s):  

2008 ◽  
Vol 11 (2) ◽  
pp. 93-103 ◽  
Author(s):  
Rom Harré
Keyword(s):  

2015 ◽  
Vol 7 (3) ◽  
pp. 105-130 ◽  
Author(s):  
Robert K. Garcia
Keyword(s):  

I aim to synthesize two issues within theistic metaphysics. The first concerns the metaphysics of creaturely properties and, more specifically, the nature of unshareable properties, or tropes. The second concerns the metaphysics of providence and, more specifically, the way in which God sustains creatures, or sustenance. I propose that creaturely properties, understood as what I call modifier tropes, are identical with divine acts of sustenance, understood as acts of property-conferral. I argue that this theistic conferralism is attractive because it integrates trope theory and the doctrine of sustenance in a mutually enhancing way. Taking modifier tropes to be divine acts mitigates certain weaknesses of trope theory and safeguards divine sustenance from the threat of both deism and occasionalism.


Author(s):  
Anna-Sofia Maurin

Trope theory is the view that the world is (wholly or partly) constituted by so-called tropes, which are entities most often characterized as a kind of abstract particular or particular property. Very little is uncontroversial when it comes to tropes and the theory or theories in which tropes (not always so-called) figure. What attracts many to the theory is that it, in occupying a sort of middle position in between classical nominalism (according to which all there is, is particular) and classical realism (according to which there is a separate and fundamental category of properties), appears to avoid some of the troubles befalling either of those views. More precisely, by accepting the existence of entities that are, or that at least behave like, properties, the trope theorist avoids the charge, often made against classical nominalists, of positing entities that are somehow too unstructured to be able to fulfill all of our explanatory needs. And by not accepting the existence of universals, the trope theorist avoids having to accept the existence of a kind of entity many find mysterious, counterintuitive, and “unscientific.” Apart from this very thin core assumption—that there are tropes—different trope theories need not have very much in common. Most trope theorists (but not all) believe that there is nothing but tropes. Most of these one-category trope theorists (but, again, not all) hold that distinct concrete particulars (which are understood by most, but again not all, as bundles of tropes) are the same—for example, have the same color—when (some of) the tropes that characterize them are members of the same (exact) similarity class. And most (but not all) hold that resemblance between tropes is determined by the tropes’ individual, intrinsic nature, which is taken as a primitive.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document