relational nouns
Recently Published Documents


TOTAL DOCUMENTS

32
(FIVE YEARS 10)

H-INDEX

5
(FIVE YEARS 1)

2021 ◽  
Vol 2 (4) ◽  
pp. 26-44
Author(s):  
Vadim Dyachkov

The paper deals with the morphology of class marking in Natioro, an underdescribed Gur language spoken in several villages of Burkina Faso. In Natioro, class markers (which are a typical feature of Gur languages) are frequently omitted in many contexts, such as genitive constructions, as well as NPs modified by adjectives, numerals, and quantifiers. In the paper, I will focus on the morphological (rather than semantic) properties of these constructions. I will show that noun stems occurring in constructions with omitted class markers can be regarded as instances of incorporation. Particular attention will be given to adjectival incorporation. In Natioro, there are two types of adjectival constructions, which can be distinguished by the nature of the stems involved. I will argue that some of the incorporated constructions are derived by merging a noun with a non-inflected adjective, whereas others can be regarded as full-fledged adjectives that incorporate noun stems. Some parallels between the constructions of the latter type and constructions with relational nouns are discussed as well.


2021 ◽  
pp. 1-37
Author(s):  
ALAN HEZAO KE ◽  
ACRISIO PIRES

This paper argues that inalienable relational nouns in Mandarin Chinese, specifically kinship nouns (KNs, e.g. father, sister) and body-part nouns (BPNs, e.g. head, face), have an implicit reflexive argument. Based on a syntactic comparison between KNs, BPNs, locally and long-distance bound reflexives, we argue that the implicit reflexive arguments of BPNs must be locally bound, whereas that of KNs can either be locally or long-distance bound. We conclude that these two types of implicit arguments in Mandarin Chinese correspond to locally and long-distance bound reflexives, respectively. We analyze this difference in connection with binding theory and a theory of logophoricity. We argue that the implicit argument of BPNs is a locally bound anaphor and cannot be used as a logophor, whereas that of KNs can, supporting a proposal that the logophoric property leads to long-distance binding, as argued by Huang & Liu’s (2001) for reflexives in Mandarin Chinese.


2020 ◽  
Vol 18 (1) ◽  
pp. 79-102
Author(s):  
Бранимир В. Станковић

The paper investigates the semantic and pragmatic properties of the postpositive definite article and demonstratives in Serbian TimokLužnice dialect. In the literature, there is a consensus on the evaluation that the definite article morpheme functions both as a demonstrative and an article (BELIĆ 1905; STANOJEVIĆ 1911; BOGDANOVIĆ 1979; ĆIRIĆ 1893) and that “the demonstrative nuances still exist in the article” (VUKADINOVIĆ 1996: 203), without a thorough analysis in what conditions the utterance receives a demonstrative or a definite interpretation. We will show that there are contexts in which either the article or the demonstrative is pragmatically acceptable for native speakers. Namely, the results of a conducted research in which the speakers evaluated the pragmatic acceptability of an utterance in a given context on a 3point Likert scale unequivocally show that the definite article is used to mark discourse-old relational nouns’ referents, uniqueness, associative anaphora and generic noun phrases, while demonstratives regularly appear with contrastive deictic referential phrases and in emphatic nonepithetic contexts.


2020 ◽  
Vol 49 (2) ◽  
Author(s):  
Doris Payne

Maa linguistic varieties (Maasai, Parakuyo, Chamus, Samburu, among others), of the Eastern Nilotic family (Nilo-Saharan phylum), have words which can modify a predicate or predication and have the function of what cross-linguistically are called adverbs. While these words can be considered a single class due to this shared function and distribution, there are nevertheless morphosyntactic and usage distinctions. This is partly due to disparate historical origins, but also to semantics and different typical collocations. Among other distinctions, some adverbs can function as nominal tense/aspect markers within a determined nominal phrase (DP). Though the origins of all adverbs cannot be traced, the paper documents sources in oblique prepositional phrases, relational nouns, adjectives, relative clauses, and perhaps infinitive verbs, involving a wide range of lexical roots, such as ‘little’, ‘paint, mark’, ‘be abundant (with grass), be generous’, and others. Some synchronic adverbs do not have evident sources in other word classes, including the ­most frequently used word for ‘previously, before’, and the modal adverb ‘probably not, unlikely’ which is also an attenuative adverb. Maa adjectives and nouns largely overlap in their morphosyntax, but the ability to be modified by certain adverbs distinguishes them.


2020 ◽  
Vol 37 (2) ◽  
pp. 179-208
Author(s):  
Toni Bassaganyas-Bars ◽  
Louise McNally

AbstractEdward Keenan coined the term “existential-have” for have-sentences containing a relational noun in object position that present a definiteness effect (DE) similar to the one in there be-sentences. We begin this paper by showing in detail that the DE in these sentences is in fact different from the one found with there be-sentences. We then explain how these contrasts reflect differences in the semantics of the two sorts of sentences that we have independently argued for in previous work. We will specifically challenge two assumptions that are frequently made about the definiteness effect in have-sentences: (1) that it is related to any version of the so-called “weak”/“strong” distinction that has been used to characterize the effect in there be-sentences; and (2) that it is limited to relational nouns like handle and follows from treating such nouns as two-place predicates. Finally, we show how our account is superior to other accounts that have been offered of the definiteness effect in have-sentences.


2019 ◽  
Vol 50 (4) ◽  
pp. 825-846 ◽  
Author(s):  
George Tsoulas ◽  
Rebecca Woods

Green (1971) notes the apparent unacceptability of certain quantificational expressions as possessors of singular head nouns. We provide data from a range of English dialects to show that such constructions are not straightforwardly unacceptable, but there are a number of restrictions on their use. We build on Kayne’s ( 1993 , 1994 ) analysis of English possessives in conjunction with considerations on floating quantifiers to explain both the types of possessive that are permitted in the relevant dialects and their distribution, which is restricted to predicative position.


2019 ◽  
Vol 45 (1) ◽  
pp. 24-43
Author(s):  
Chyan-an Arthur Wang
Keyword(s):  

Abstract The possessive construction in Mandarin is similar to English prenominal possessives except that maximality is presupposed only for cases involving inherently relational nouns. In this paper, I adopt the hypothesized split of argument and modifier genitives proposed by Partee & Borschev (2001, 2003) and argue that modifier-genitives can occur NP-internally in Mandarin possessives, whose appearance is restricted to cases with non-relational nouns. The discrepancy of the maximality presupposition observed in Mandarin can thus be captured since non-relational nouns can have a split of interpretations between argument and modifier genitives, resulting in a non-maximality reading.


2019 ◽  
Vol 48 (4) ◽  
pp. 819-842
Author(s):  
Alan Hezao Ke ◽  
Ya Zhao ◽  
Liqun Gao ◽  
Shuying Liu ◽  
Acrisio Pires

Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document