arithmetical interpretation
Recently Published Documents


TOTAL DOCUMENTS

12
(FIVE YEARS 1)

H-INDEX

5
(FIVE YEARS 0)

Author(s):  
Víctor Aranda

The aim of this paper is to clarify why propositional logic is Post complete and its weak completeness was almost unnoticed by Hilbert and Bernays, while first-order logic is Post incomplete and its weak completeness was seen as an open problem by Hilbert and Ackermman. Thus, I will compare propositional and first-order logic in the Prinzipien der Mathematik, Bernays’s second Habilitationsschrift and the Grundzüge der Theoretischen Logik. The so called “arithmetical interpretation”, the conjunctive and disjunctive normal forms and the soundness of the propositional rules of inference deserve special emphasis.


2012 ◽  
Vol 6 (1) ◽  
pp. 129-146 ◽  
Author(s):  
TAISHI KURAHASHI

AbstractSolovay proved the arithmetical completeness theorem for the system GL of propositional modal logic of provability. Montagna proved that this completeness does not hold for a natural extension QGL of GL to the predicate modal logic. Let Th(QGL) be the set of all theorems of QGL, Fr(QGL) be the set of all formulas valid in all transitive and conversely well-founded Kripke frames, and let PL(T) be the set of all predicate modal formulas provable in Tfor any arithmetical interpretation. Montagna’s results are described as Th(QGL) ⊊ (Fr(QGL), PL(PA) ⊈ Fr(QGL), and Th(QGL) ⊊ PL(PA).In this paper, we prove the following three theorems: (1) Fr(QGL) ⊈ PL(T) for any Σ1-sound recursively enumerable extension T of I Σ1, (2) PL(T) ⊈ Fr(QGL) for any recursively enumerable A-theory T extending I Σ1, and (3) Th(QGL) ⊊ Fr(QGL) ∩ PL(T) for any recursively enumerable A-theory T extending I Σ2.To prove these theorems, we use iterated consistency assertions and nonstandard models of arithmetic, and we improve Artemov’s lemma which is used to prove Vardanyan’s theorem on the Π02-completeness of PL(T).


2006 ◽  
Vol 17 (02) ◽  
pp. 143-155 ◽  
Author(s):  
ANTON DEITMAR ◽  
J. WILLIAM HOFFMAN

A weak version of the Ihara formula is proved for zeta functions attached to quotients of the Bruhat–Tits building of PGL3. This formula expresses the zeta function in terms of Hecke-operators. It is the first step towards an arithmetical interpretation of the combinatorially defined zeta function.


1997 ◽  
Vol 7 (6) ◽  
pp. 639-662 ◽  
Author(s):  
KOSTA DOšEN ◽  
ZORAN PETRIĆ

This paper presents a new and self-contained proof of a result characterizing objects isomorphic in the free symmetric monoidal closed category, i.e., objects isomorphic in every symmetric monoidal closed category. This characterization is given by a finitely axiomatizable and decidable equational calculus, which differs from the calculus that axiomatizes all arithmetical equalities in the language with 1, product and exponentiation by lacking 1c=1 and (a · b)c =ac · bc (the latter calculus characterizes objects isomorphic in the free cartesian closed category). Nevertheless, this calculus is complete for a certain arithmetical interpretation, and its arithmetical completeness plays an essential role in the proof given here of its completeness with respect to symmetric monoidal closed isomorphisms.


1991 ◽  
Vol 1 (1) ◽  
pp. 71-89 ◽  
Author(s):  
Mikael Rittri

AbstractA method is proposed to search for an identifier in a functional program library by using its Hindley–Milner type as a key. This can be seen as an approximation of using the specification as a key.Functions that only differ in their argument order or currying are essentially the same, which is expressed by a congruence relation on types. During a library search, congruent types are identified. If a programmer is not satisfied with the type of a found value, he can use a conversion function (like curry), which must exist between congruent types, to convert the value into the type of his choice.Types are congruent if they are isomorphic in all cartesian closed categories. To put it more simply, types are congruent if they are equal under an arithmetical interpretation, with cartesian product as multiplication and function space as exponentiation. This congruence relation is characterized by seven equational axioms. There is a simple term-rewriting algorithm to decide congruence, using which a search system has been implemented for the functional language Lazy ML, with good performance.The congruence relation can also be used as a basis for other search strategies, e.g. searching for identifiers of a more general type, modulo congruence or allowing free type variables in queries.


1990 ◽  
Vol 55 (3) ◽  
pp. 1090-1098 ◽  
Author(s):  
Sergei Artemov ◽  
Giorgie Dzhaparidze

AbstractThe paper proves a predicate version of Solovay's well-known theorem on provability interpretations of modal logic:If a closed modal predicate-logical formula R is not valid in some finite Kripke model, then there exists an arithmetical interpretation f such that PA ⊬ fR.This result implies the arithmetical completeness of arithmetically correct modal predicate logics with the finite model property (including the one-variable fragments of QGL and QS). The proof was obtained by adding “the predicate part” as a specific addition to the standard Solovay construction.


1984 ◽  
Vol 49 (3) ◽  
pp. 935-942 ◽  
Author(s):  
Arnon Avron

We deal here with two modal logics, GL and Grz, that are known to have interesting arithmetical interpretations connected with the notion of provability. GL is the extensiom of K (or K4) by the schema □(□ A → A) → □ A, and Grz is the extension of S4 by □(□(A → □A) →A) → □A. GL is also known to be sound and complete with respect to the class of all Kripke models that are transitive, irreflexive and well founded. Grz bears the same relation to the corresponding reflexive models. We refer the reader to [1] for a full exposition of the subject. (See also [4], [2], [6].)In §I we develop a sequential calculus for both GL and Grz and give a semantical proof that both systems admit cut-elimination. (Incidentally, this provides an easy proof of the semantical completeness of the two systems.) With respect to GL this yields a correction of an error in [2].In §II we show that cut-elimination fails for QGL (the extension of GL to a language with quantifiers). We further show that, despite this failure, QGL still has some of GL's interesting properties (e.g., the disjunction property). We also show, using fixed-point techniques, that similar properties obtain if we take as semantics for QGL the arithmetical interpretation extended in the obvious way.We want to thank Professor H. Gaifman for his help while working on the subject.


1983 ◽  
Vol 48 (3) ◽  
pp. 704-713 ◽  
Author(s):  
Petr Hájek

AbstractAn arithmetical interpretation of dynamic propositional logic (DPL) is a mapping ƒ satisfying the following: (1) ƒ associates with each formula A of DPL a sentence ƒ(A) of Peano arithmetic (PA) and with each program α a formula ƒ(α) of PA with one free variable describing formally a supertheory of PA; (2) ƒ commutes with logical connectives; (3) ƒ([α]A) is the sentence saying that ƒ(A) is provable in the theory ƒ(α); (4) for each axiom A of DPL, ƒ(A) is provable in PA (and consequently, for each A provable in DPL, ƒ(A) is provable in PA). The arithmetical completeness theorem is proved saying that a formula A of DPL is provable in DPL iff for each arithmetical interpretation ƒ, ƒ(A) is provable in PA. Various modifications of this result are considered.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document