scholarly journals An analytic proof of the Borwein Conjecture

2021 ◽  
pp. 108028
Author(s):  
Chen Wang
Keyword(s):  
1996 ◽  
Vol 07 (01) ◽  
pp. 1-17
Author(s):  
GUANG-YUAN GUO

We give an analytic proof of a result by Donaldson which asserts that there is a one to one correspondence between the moduli space of framed instantons on S4 and the moduli space of holomorphic bundles over CP2 trivialized along a line.


1995 ◽  
Vol 18 (2) ◽  
pp. 295-299 ◽  
Author(s):  
Junjiro Noguchi
Keyword(s):  

1952 ◽  
Vol 2 (2) ◽  
pp. 231-242
Author(s):  
Robert Steinberg ◽  
Raymond Redheffer
Keyword(s):  

2019 ◽  
pp. 502-543
Author(s):  
Paul Rusnock ◽  
Jan Šebestík

This chapter presents an overview of Bolzano’s work in mathematics and its philosophy, while presenting some interesting samples of his work. It begins with a discussion of his views on mathematical method in their historical context, followed by an exposition of some of his best work in real analysis. In particular, the chapter discusses his early work on infinite series and his analysis of continuity, beginning with the Purely Analytic Proof (1817), and extending to his construction of a continuous, nowhere differentiable function in the 1830s, called Bolzano’s function. (85 words)


Author(s):  
I. Grattan-Guinness

The term ‘mathematical analysis’ refers to the major branch of mathematics which is concerned with the theory of functions and includes the differential and integral calculus. Analysis and the calculus began as the study of curves, calculus being concerned with tangents to and areas under curves. The focus was shifted to functions following the insight, due to Leibniz and Isaac Newton in the second half of the seventeenth century, that a curve is the graph of a function. Algebraic foundations were proposed by Lagrange in the late eighteenth century; assuming that any function always took an expansion in a power series, he defined the derivatives from the coefficients of the terms. In the 1820s his assumption was refuted by Cauchy, who had already launched a fourth approach, like Newton’s based on limits, but formulated much more carefully. It was refined further by Weierstrass, by means which helped to create set theory. Analysis also encompasses the theory of limits and of the convergence and divergence of infinite series; modern versions also use point set topology. It has taken various forms over the centuries, of which the older ones are still represented in some notations and terms. Philosophical issues include the status of infinitesimals, the place of logic in the articulation of proofs, types of definition, and the (non-) relationship to analytic proof methods.


1978 ◽  
Vol 21 (2) ◽  
pp. 247-248
Author(s):  
P. E. Kopp

Nagel [3] has given a purely functional-analytic proof of Akcoglu and Sucheston's operator version [1] of the Blum-Hanson theorem. The purpose of this note is to show that the same techniques may be applied to obtain a proof, in the context of (AL)-spaces, of a more general result due to Fong and Sucheston [2]. By Kakutani's representation theorem, any (AL)-space can of course be represented as an L-1-space. Thus the present result is simply a reformulation of that of Fong and Sucheston.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document