scholarly journals Quantum communication complexity of distribution testing

2021 ◽  
Vol 21 (15&16) ◽  
pp. 1261-1273
Author(s):  
Aleksandrs Belovs ◽  
Arturo Castellanos ◽  
Francois Le Gall ◽  
Guillaume Malod ◽  
Alexander A. Sherstov

The classical communication complexity of testing closeness of discrete distributions has recently been studied by Andoni, Malkin and Nosatzki (ICALP'19). In this problem, two players each receive $t$ samples from one distribution over $[n]$, and the goal is to decide whether their two distributions are equal, or are $\epsilon$-far apart in the $l_1$-distance. In the present paper we show that the quantum communication complexity of this problem is $\tilde{O}(n/(t\epsilon^2))$ qubits when the distributions have low $l_2$-norm, which gives a quadratic improvement over the classical communication complexity obtained by Andoni, Malkin and Nosatzki. We also obtain a matching lower bound by using the pattern matrix method. Let us stress that the samples received by each of the parties are classical, and it is only communication between them that is quantum. Our results thus give one setting where quantum protocols overcome classical protocols for a testing problem with purely classical samples.

2011 ◽  
Vol 11 (7&8) ◽  
pp. 574-591
Author(s):  
Ashley Montanaro

We present a new example of a partial boolean function whose one-way quantum communication complexity is exponentially lower than its one-way classical communication complexity. The problem is a natural generalisation of the previously studied Subgroup Membership problem: Alice receives a bit string $x$, Bob receives a permutation matrix $M$, and their task is to determine whether $Mx=x$ or $Mx$ is far from $x$. The proof uses Fourier analysis and an inequality of Kahn, Kalai and Linial.


2017 ◽  
Vol 17 (1&2) ◽  
pp. 106-116
Author(s):  
Jop Briet ◽  
Jeroen Zuiddam

After Bob sends Alice a bit, she responds with a lengthy reply. At the cost of a factor of two in the total communication, Alice could just as well have given Bob her two possible replies at once without listening to him at all, and have him select which one applies. Motivated by a conjecture stating that this form of “round elimination” is impossible in exact quantum communication complexity, we study the orthogonal rank and a symmetric variant thereof for a certain family of Cayley graphs. The orthogonal rank of a graph is the smallest number d for which one can label each vertex with a nonzero d-dimensional complex vector such that adjacent vertices receive orthogonal vectors. We show an exp(n) lower bound on the orthogonal rank of the graph on {0, 1} n in which two strings are adjacent if they have Hamming distance at least n/2. In combination with previous work, this implies an affirmative answer to the above conjecture.


2016 ◽  
Vol 113 (12) ◽  
pp. 3191-3196 ◽  
Author(s):  
Harry Buhrman ◽  
Łukasz Czekaj ◽  
Andrzej Grudka ◽  
Michał Horodecki ◽  
Paweł Horodecki ◽  
...  

We obtain a general connection between a large quantum advantage in communication complexity and Bell nonlocality. We show that given any protocol offering a sufficiently large quantum advantage in communication complexity, there exists a way of obtaining measurement statistics that violate some Bell inequality. Our main tool is port-based teleportation. If the gap between quantum and classical communication complexity can grow arbitrarily large, the ratio of the quantum value to the classical value of the Bell quantity becomes unbounded with the increase in the number of inputs and outputs.


2009 ◽  
Vol 9 (5&6) ◽  
pp. 444-460
Author(s):  
Y.-Y. Shi ◽  
Y.-F. Zhu

A major open problem in communication complexity is whether or not quantum protocols can be exponentially more efficient than classical ones for computing a {\em total} Boolean function in the two-party interactive model. Razborov's result ({\em Izvestiya: Mathematics}, 67(1):145--159, 2002) implies the conjectured negative answer for functions $F$ of the following form: $F(x, y)=f_n(x_1\cdot y_1, x_2\cdot y_2, ..., x_n\cdot y_n)$, where $f_n$ is a {\em symmetric} Boolean function on $n$ Boolean inputs, and $x_i$, $y_i$ are the $i$'th bit of $x$ and $y$, respectively. His proof critically depends on the symmetry of $f_n$. We develop a lower-bound method that does not require symmetry and prove the conjecture for a broader class of functions. Each of those functions $F$ is the ``block-composition'' of a ``building block'' $g_k : \{0, 1\}^k \times \{0, 1\}^k \rightarrow \{0, 1\}$, and an $f_n : \{0, 1\}^n \rightarrow \{0, 1\}$, such that $F(x, y) = f_n( g_k(x_1, y_1), g_k(x_2, y_2), ..., g_k(x_n, y_n) )$, where $x_i$ and $y_i$ are the $i$'th $k$-bit block of $x, y\in\{0, 1\}^{nk}$, respectively. We show that as long as g_k itself is "hard'' enough, its block-composition with an arbitrary f_n has polynomially related quantum and classical communication complexities. For example, when g_k is the Inner Product function with k=\Omega(\log n), the deterministic communication complexity of its block-composition with any f_n is asymptotically at most the quantum complexity to the power of 7.


2015 ◽  
Vol 27 (3) ◽  
pp. 311-331 ◽  
Author(s):  
JOZEF GRUSKA ◽  
DAOWEN QIU ◽  
SHENGGEN ZHENG

In the distributed Deutsch–Jozsa promise problem, two parties are to determine whether their respective strings x, y ∈ {0,1}n are at the Hamming distanceH(x, y) = 0 or H(x, y) = $\frac{n}{2}$. Buhrman et al. (STOC' 98) proved that the exact quantum communication complexity of this problem is O(log n) while the deterministic communication complexity is Ω(n). This was the first impressive (exponential) gap between quantum and classical communication complexity. In this paper, we generalize the above distributed Deutsch–Jozsa promise problem to determine, for any fixed $\frac{n}{2}$ ⩽ k ⩽ n, whether H(x, y) = 0 or H(x, y) = k, and show that an exponential gap between exact quantum and deterministic communication complexity still holds if k is an even such that $\frac{1}{2}$n ⩽ k < (1 − λ)n, where 0 < λ < $\frac{1}{2}$ is given. We also deal with a promise version of the well-known disjointness problem and show also that for this promise problem there exists an exponential gap between quantum (and also probabilistic) communication complexity and deterministic communication complexity of the promise version of such a disjointness problem. Finally, some applications to quantum, probabilistic and deterministic finite automata of the results obtained are demonstrated.


2015 ◽  
Vol 30 (01) ◽  
pp. 1530001 ◽  
Author(s):  
Alberto Montina

In this review, we discuss a relation between quantum communication complexity and a long-standing debate in quantum foundation concerning the interpretation of the quantum state. Is the quantum state a physical element of reality as originally interpreted by Schrödinger? Or is it an abstract mathematical object containing statistical information about the outcome of measurements as interpreted by Born? Although these questions sound philosophical and pointless, they can be made precise in the framework of what we call classical theories of quantum processes, which are a reword of quantum phenomena in the language of classical probability theory. In 2012, Pusey, Barrett and Rudolph (PBR) proved, under an assumption of preparation independence, a theorem supporting the original interpretation of Schrödinger in the classical framework. The PBR theorem has attracted considerable interest revitalizing the debate and motivating other proofs with alternative hypotheses. Recently, we showed that these questions are related to a practical problem in quantum communication complexity, namely, quantifying the minimal amount of classical communication required in the classical simulation of a two-party quantum communication process. In particular, we argued that the statement of the PBR theorem can be proved if the classical communication cost of simulating the communication of n qubits grows more than exponentially in n. Our argument is based on an assumption that we call probability equipartition property. This property is somehow weaker than the preparation independence property used in the PBR theorem, as the former can be justified by the latter and the asymptotic equipartition property of independent stochastic sources. The probability equipartition property is a general and natural hypothesis that can be assumed even if the preparation independence hypothesis is dropped. In this review, we further develop our argument into the form of a theorem.


Quantum ◽  
2018 ◽  
Vol 2 ◽  
pp. 72 ◽  
Author(s):  
Sophie Laplante ◽  
Mathieu Laurière ◽  
Alexandre Nolin ◽  
Jérémie Roland ◽  
Gabriel Senno

The question of how large Bell inequality violations can be, for quantum distributions, has been the object of much work in the past several years. We say that a Bell inequality is normalized if its absolute value does not exceed 1 for any classical (i.e. local) distribution. Upper and (almost) tight lower bounds have been given for the quantum violation of these Bell inequalities in terms of number of outputs of the distribution, number of inputs, and the dimension of the shared quantum states. In this work, we revisit normalized Bell inequalities together with another family: inefficiency-resistant Bell inequalities. To be inefficiency-resistant, the Bell value must not exceed 1 for any local distribution, including those that can abort. This makes the Bell inequality resistant to the detection loophole, while a normalized Bell inequality is resistant to general local noise. Both these families of Bell inequalities are closely related to communication complexity lower bounds. We show how to derive large violations from any gap between classical and quantum communication complexity, provided the lower bound on classical communication is proven using these lower bound techniques. This leads to inefficiency-resistant violations that can be exponential in the size of the inputs. Finally, we study resistance to noise and inefficiency for these Bell inequalities.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document