Reducibility of partial recursive functions. II

1978 ◽  
Vol 18 (4) ◽  
pp. 541-548
Author(s):  
A. N. D�gtev
Author(s):  
David J. Lobina

Recursion, or the capacity of ‘self-reference’, has played a central role within mathematical approaches to understanding the nature of computation, from the general recursive functions of Alonzo Church to the partial recursive functions of Stephen C. Kleene and the production systems of Emil Post. Recursion has also played a significant role in the analysis and running of certain computational processes within computer science (viz., those with self-calls and deferred operations). Yet the relationship between the mathematical and computer versions of recursion is subtle and intricate. A recursively specified algorithm, for example, may well proceed iteratively if time and space constraints permit; but the nature of specific data structures—viz., recursive data structures—will also return a recursive solution as the most optimal process. In other words, the correspondence between recursive structures and recursive processes is not automatic; it needs to be demonstrated on a case-by-case basis.


1975 ◽  
Vol 20 (2) ◽  
pp. 146-158 ◽  
Author(s):  
P. Aczel

The notion of a recursive density type (R.D.T.) was introduced by Medvedev and developed by Pavlova (1961). More recently the algebra of R.D.T.'s was initiated by Gonshor and Rice (1969). The R.D.T.'s are equivalence classes of sets of integers, similar in many respects to the R.E.T.'s. They may both be thought of as effective analogues of the cardinal numbers. While the equivalence relationfor R.E.T.'s is defined in terms of partial recursive functions, that for R.D.T.'s may be characterized in terms of recursively bounded partial functions (see 4.22a).


1956 ◽  
Vol 21 (4) ◽  
pp. 337-346 ◽  
Author(s):  
Frederic B. Fitch

1.1 The system K* of basic logic, as presented in a previous paper, will be shown to be formalizable in an alternative way according to which the rule [E],is replaced by the rule [F],1.2. General recursive functions will be shown to be definable in K* in a way that retains functional notation, so that the equation,will be formalized in K* by the formula,where ‘f’, ‘p1’, … ‘pn’ respectively denote φ, x1, …, xn, and where ‘≐’ plays the role of numerical equality. Partial recursive functions may be handled in a similar way. The rule [E] is not required for dealing with primitive recursive functions by this method.1.3. An operator ‘G’ will be defined such that ‘[Ga ≐ p]’ is a theorem of K* if and only if ‘p’ denotes the Gödel number of ‘a’.1.4. In reformulating K* we assume ‘o0’, ‘o1,’ ‘o2’, …, have been so chosen that we can determine effectively whether or not a given U-expression is the mth member of the above series. The revised rules for K* are then as follows. (Double-arrow forms of these rules are derivable, except in the case of rule [V].)


1998 ◽  
Vol 63 (4) ◽  
pp. 1201-1217
Author(s):  
Norman Feldman

In this paper we consider the three-valued logic used by Kleene [6] in the theory of partial recursive functions. This logic has three truth values: true (T), false (F), and undefined (U). One interpretation of U is as follows: Suppose we have two partially recursive predicates P(x) and Q(x) and we want to know the truth value of P(x) ∧ Q(x) for a particular x0. If x0 is in the domain of definition of both P and Q, then P(x0) ∧ Q(x0) is true if both P(x0) and Q(x0) are true, and false otherwise. But what if x0 is not in the domain of definition of P, but is in the domain of definition of Q? There are several choices, but the one chosen by Kleene is that if Q(X0) is false, then P(x0) ∧ Q(x0) is also false and if Q(X0) is true, then P(x0) ∧ Q(X0) is undefined.What arises is the question about knowledge of whether or not x0 is in the domain of definition of P. Is there an effective procedure to determine this? If not, then we can interpret U as being unknown. If there is an effective procedure, then our decision for the truth value for P(x) ∧ Q(x) is based on the knowledge that is not in the domain of definition of P. In this case, U can be interpreted as undefined. In either case, we base our truth value of P(x) ∧ Q(x) on the truth value of Q(X0).


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document