Some properties of the syntactic p-recursion categories generated by consistent, recursively enumerable extensions of Peano arithmetic.

1991 ◽  
Vol 56 (2) ◽  
pp. 643-660 ◽  
Author(s):  
Robert A. Di Paola ◽  
Franco Montagna

The dominical categories were introduced by Di Paola and Heller, as a first step toward a category-theoretic treatment of the generalized first Godel incompleteness theorem [1]. In his Ph.D. dissertation [7], Rosolini subsequently defined the closely related p-categories, which should prove pertinent to category-theoretic representations of incompleteness for intuitionistic systems. The precise relationship between these two concepts is as follows: every dominical category is a pointed p-category, but there are p-categories, indeed pointed p-isotypes (all pairs of objects being isomorphic) with a Turing morphism that are not dominical. The first of these assertions is an easy consequence of the fact that in a dominical category C by definition the near product functor when restricted to the subcategory Ct, of total morphisms of C (as “total” is defined in [1]) constitutes a bona fide product such that the derived associativity and commutativity isomorphisms are natural on C × C × C and C × C, respectively, as noted in [7]. As to the second, p-recursion categories (that is, pointed p-isotypes having a Turing morphism) that are not dominical were defined and studied by Montagna in [6], the syntactic p-categories ST and S′T associated with consistent, recursively enumerable extensions of Peano arithmetic, PA. These merit detailed investigation on several counts.

2021 ◽  
Vol 18 (5) ◽  
pp. 380-400
Author(s):  
Robert Meyer ◽  
Chris Mortensen

This paper develops in certain directions the work of Meyer in [3], [4], [5] and [6] (see also Routley [10] and Asenjo [11]). In those works, Peano’s axioms for arithmetic were formulated with a logical base of the relevant logic R, and it was proved finitistically that the resulting arithmetic, called R♯, was absolutely consistent. It was pointed out that such a result escapes incau- tious formulations of Goedel’s second incompleteness theorem, and provides a basis for a revived Hilbert programme. The absolute consistency result used as a model arithmetic modulo two. Modulo arithmetics are not or- dinarily thought of as an extension of Peano arithmetic, since some of the propositions of the latter, such as that zero is the successor of no number, fail in the former. Consequently a logical base which, unlike classical logic, tolerates contradictory theories was used for the model. The logical base for the model was the three-valued logic RM3 (see e.g. [1] or [8]), which has the advantage that while it is an extension of R, it is finite valued and so easier to handle. The resulting model-theoretic structure (called in this paper RM32) is interesting in its own right in that the set of sentences true therein consti- tutes a negation inconsistent but absolutely consistent arithmetic which is an extension of R♯. In fact, in the light of the result of [6], it is an extension of Peano arithmetic with a base of a classical logic, P♯. A generalisation of the structure is to modulo arithmetics with the same logical base RM3, but with varying moduli (called RM3i here). We first study the properties of these arithmetics in this paper. The study is then generalised by vary- ing the logical base, to give the arithmetics RMni, of logical base RMn and modulus i. Not all of these exist, however, as arithmetical properties and logical properties interact, as we will show. The arithmetics RMni give rise, on intersection, to an inconsistent arithmetic RMω which is not of modulo i for any i. We also study its properties, and, among other results, we show by finitistic means that the more natural relevant arithmetics R♯ and R♯♯ are incomplete (whether or not consistent and recursively enumerable). In the rest of the paper we apply these techniques to several topics, particularly relevant quantum arithmetic in which we are able to show (unlike classical quantum arithmetic) that the law of distribution remains unprovable. Aside from its intrinsic interest, we regard the present exercise as a demonstration that inconsistent theories and models are of mathematical worth and interest.


1999 ◽  
Vol 64 (4) ◽  
pp. 1407-1425
Author(s):  
Claes Strannegård

AbstractWe investigate the modal logic of interpretability over Peano arithmetic. Our main result is a compactness theorem that extends the arithmetical completeness theorem for the interpretability logic ILMω. This extension concerns recursively enumerable sets of formulas of interpretability logic (rather than single formulas). As corollaries we obtain a uniform arithmetical completeness theorem for the interpretability logic ILM and a partial answer to a question of Orey from 1961. After some simplifications, we also obtain Shavrukov's embedding theorem for Magari algebras (a.k.a. diagonalizable algebras).


Author(s):  
Raymond M. Smullyan

Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem, roughly stated, is that if Peano Arithmetic is consistent, then it cannot prove its own consistency. The theorem has been generalized and abstracted in various ways and this has led to the notion of a provability predicate, which plays a fundamental role in much modern metamathematical research. To this notion we now turn. A formula P(v1) is called a provability predicate for S if for all sentences X and Y the following three conditions hold: Suppose now P(v1) is a Σ1-formula that expresses the set P of the system P.A. Under the assumption of ω-consistency, P(v1) represents P in P.A. Under the weaker assumption of simple consistency, all that follows is that P(v1) represents some superset of P, but that is enough to imply that if X is provable in P.A., then so is P (x̄).


1984 ◽  
Vol 49 (3) ◽  
pp. 917-929 ◽  
Author(s):  
Robert K. Meyer ◽  
Chris Mortensen

This paper develops in certain directions the work of Meyer in [3], [4], [5] and [6] (see also Routley [10] and Asenjo [11]). In those works, Peano's axioms for arithmetic were formulated with a logical base of the relevant logic R, and it was proved finitistically that the resulting arithmetic, called R#, was absolutely consistent. It was pointed out that such a result escapes incautious formulations of Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, and provides a basis for a revived Hilbert programme. The absolute consistency result used as a model arithmetic modulo two. Modulo arithmetics are not ordinarily thought of as an extension of Peano arithmetic, since some of the propositions of the latter, such as that zero is the successor of no number, fail in the former. Consequently a logical base which, unlike classical logic, tolerates contradictory theories was used for the model. The logical base for the model was the three-valued logic RM3 (see e.g. [1] or [8]), which has the advantage that while it is an extension of R, it is finite valued and so easier to handle.The resulting model-theoretic structure (called in this paper RM32) is interesting in its own right in that the set of sentences true therein constitutes a negation inconsistent but absolutely consistent arithmetic which is an extension of R#. In fact, in the light of the result of [6], it is an extension of Peano arithmetic with a base of a classical logic, P#. A generalisation of the structure is to modulo arithmetics with the same logical base RM3, but with varying moduli (called RM3i here).


1974 ◽  
Vol 39 (1) ◽  
pp. 95-96 ◽  
Author(s):  
Carl G. Jockusch

Let be the collection of all sets which are finite Boolean combinations of recursively enumerable (r.e.) sets of numbers. Dale Myers asked [private correspondence] whether there exists a nonempty class of sets containing no member of . In this note we construct such a class. The motivation for Myers' question was his observation (reported in [1]) that the existence of such a class is equivalent to the assertion that there is a finite consistent set of tiles which has no m-trial tiling of the plane for any m (obeying the “origin constraint”). (For explanations of these terms and further results on tilings of the plane, cf. [1] and [5].) In addition to the application to tilings, the proof of our results gives some information on bi-immune sets and on complete extensions of first-order Peano arithmetic.A class of sets may be roughly described as the class of infinite binary input tapes for which a fixed Turing machine fails to halt, or alternatively as the class of infinite branches of a recursive tree of finite binary sequences. (In these definitions, sets of numbers are identified with the corresponding binary sequences.) Precise definitions, as well as many results concerning such classes, may be found in [3] and [4].


1983 ◽  
Vol 48 (3) ◽  
pp. 777-789 ◽  
Author(s):  
David Guaspari

We begin with a simple observation and a simple question. If we fix Th(x), some reasonable formulation of “x is the Gödel number of a theorem of Peano Arithmetic”, then for any sentence σ, Peano Arithmetic proves σ → Th(⌈σ⌉). (Here ⌈σ⌉ is the canonical term denoting the Gödel number of σ.) This observation is crucial to the proof of the Second Incompleteness Theorem. Call ψ a self-prover (with respect to Th(x)) if ψ → Th(⌈ψ⌉) is a theorem of Peano Arithmetic (from now on, PA). Our simple question is this: Does the observation have a converse—must every self-prover be provably equivalent to a sentence? Whatever φ happens to be, the formula φ ∧ Th(⌈φ⌉) is a self-prover. This makes it seem clear that there must exist self-provers which are not provably : We need only use a suitably complicated φ.Deciding what sort of complication is “suitable” and finding such a φ is surprisingly annoying. Here is a quick example: One might guess that any φ which is unprovable and would work. In that case we could take φ to be CON—that is, ¬Th(⌈0 = 1⌉); but CON ∧ Th(⌈CON⌉) is refutable in PA, so is provably equivalent to the quantifier-free formula 0 = 1.


Author(s):  
Raymond M. Smullyan

§1. By an arithmetic term or formula, we mean a term or formula in which the exponential symbol E does not appear, and by an arithmetic relation (or set), we mean a relation (set) expressible by an arithmetic formula. By the axiom system P.A. (Peano Arithmetic), we mean the system P.E. with axiom schemes N10 and N11 deleted, and in the remaining axiom schemes, terms and formulas are understood to be arithmetic terms and formulas. The system P.A. is the more usual object of modern study (indeed, the system P.E. is rarely considered in the literature). We chose to give the incompleteness proof for P.E. first since it is the simpler. In this chapter, we will prove the incompleteness of P.A. and establish several other results that will be needed in later chapters. The incompleteness of P.A. will easily follow from the incompleteness of P.E., once we show that the relation xy = z is not only Arithmetic but arithmetic (definable from plus and times alone). We will first have to show that certain other relations are arithmetic, and as we are at it, we will show stronger results about these relations that will be needed, not for the incompleteness proof of this chapter, but for several chapters that follow—we will sooner or later need to show that certain key relations are not only arithmetic, but belong to a much narrower class of relations, the Σ1-relations, which we will shortly define. These relations are the same as those known as recursively enumerable. Before defining the Σ1-relations, we turn to a still narrower class, the Σ0-relations, that will play a key role in our later development of recursive function theory. §2. We now define the classes of Σ0-formulas and Σ0-relations and then the Σ1-formulas and relations. By an atomic Σ0-formula, we shall mean a formula of one of the four forms c1 + c2 = c3, c1 · c2 =c3, c1 = c2 or c1 ≤ c2, where each of c1, c2 or c3 is either a variable or a numeral (but some may be variables and others numerals).


1963 ◽  
Vol 28 (4) ◽  
pp. 273-278 ◽  
Author(s):  
Donald A. Martin

Let be the class of recursively enumerable (r.e.) sets with infinite complements. A set M ϵ is maximal if every superset of M which is in is only finitely different from M. In [1] Friedberg shows that maximal sets exist, and it is an easy consequence of this fact that every non-simple set in has a maximal superset. The natural question which arises is whether or not this is also true for every simple set (Ullian [2]). In the present paper this question is answered negatively. However, the main concern of this paper is with demonstrating, and developing a few consequences of, what might be called the “density” of hyperhypersimple sets.


2017 ◽  
Vol 10 (4) ◽  
pp. 603-616 ◽  
Author(s):  
MAKOTO KIKUCHI ◽  
TAISHI KURAHASHI

AbstractIt is well known that Gödel’s incompleteness theorems hold for ∑1-definable theories containing Peano arithmetic. We generalize Gödel’s incompleteness theorems for arithmetically definable theories. First, we prove that every ∑n+1-definable ∑n-sound theory is incomplete. Secondly, we generalize and improve Jeroslow and Hájek’s results. That is, we prove that every consistent theory having ∏n+1 set of theorems has a true but unprovable ∏n sentence. Lastly, we prove that no ∑n+1-definable ∑n -sound theory can prove its own ∑n-soundness. These three results are generalizations of Rosser’s improvement of the first incompleteness theorem, Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem, and the second incompleteness theorem, respectively.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document