stationary subset
Recently Published Documents


TOTAL DOCUMENTS

19
(FIVE YEARS 1)

H-INDEX

5
(FIVE YEARS 0)

2019 ◽  
Vol 84 (02) ◽  
pp. 684-703
Author(s):  
THOMAS GILTON ◽  
JOHN KRUEGER

AbstractWe prove from the existence of a Mahlo cardinal the consistency of the statement that 2ω = ω3 holds and every stationary subset of ${\omega _2}\mathop \cap \nolimits {\rm{cof}}\left( \omega \right)$ reflects to an ordinal less than ω2 with cofinality ω1.


2013 ◽  
Vol 78 (3) ◽  
pp. 681-707
Author(s):  
M. C. Stanley

AbstractUsing square sequences, a stationary subset ST of אω1+1 is constructed from a tree T of height ω1, uniformly in T. Under suitable hypotheses, adding a closed unbounded subset to ST requires adding a cofinal branch to T or collapsing at least one of ω1, אω1, and אω1+1. An application is that in ZFC there is no parameter free definition of the family of subsets of אω1+1 that have a closed unbounded subset in some ω1, אω1, and אω1+1 preserving outer model.


2013 ◽  
Vol 78 (2) ◽  
pp. 667-680 ◽  
Author(s):  
Yo Matsubara ◽  
Toshimichi Usuba

AbstractWe introduce the notion of skinniness for subsets of and its variants, namely skinnier and skinniest. We show that under some cardinal arithmetical assumptions, precipitousness or 2λ-saturation of NSκλ ∣ X, where NSκλ denotes the non-stationary ideal over , implies the existence of a skinny stationary subset of X. We also show that if λ is a singular cardinal, then there is no skinnier stationary subset of . Furthermore, if λ is a strong limit singular cardinal, there is no skinny stationary subset of . Combining these results, we show that if λ is a strong limit singular cardinal, then NSκλ ∣ X can satisfy neither precipitousness nor 2λ-saturation for every stationary X ⊆ . We also indicate that , where , is equivalent to the existence of a skinnier (or skinniest) stationary subset of under some cardinal arithmetical hypotheses.


2011 ◽  
Vol 11 (01) ◽  
pp. 29-59 ◽  
Author(s):  
JOHN KRUEGER ◽  
ERNEST SCHIMMERLING

We prove that the following two statements are equiconsistent: there exists a greatly Mahlo cardinal; there exists a regular uncountable cardinal κ such that no stationary subset of κ+ ∩ cof (κ) carries a partial square.


2008 ◽  
Vol 73 (1) ◽  
pp. 181-192 ◽  
Author(s):  
Hiroshi Sakai

AbstractWe study the relationship between the semistationary reflection principle and stationary reflection principles. We show that for all regular cardinals λ ≥ ω2 the semistationary reflection principle in the space [λ]ω implies that every stationary subset of ≔ {α ∈ λ ∣ cf(α) = ω} reflects. We also show that for all cardinals λ ≥ ω3 the semistationary reflection principle in [λ]ω does not imply the stationary reflection principle in [λ]ω.


2003 ◽  
Vol 68 (4) ◽  
pp. 1163-1170 ◽  
Author(s):  
Sy D. Friedman

AbstractA classic result of Baumgartner-Harrington-Kleinberg [1] implies that assuming CH a stationary subset of ω1 has a CUB subset in a cardinal-perserving generic extension of V, via a forcing of cardinality ω1. Therefore, assuming that ω2L is countable: {X ∈ L ∣ X ⊆ ω1L and X has a CUB subset in a cardinal-preserving extension of L} is constructive, as it equals the set of constructible subsets of ω1L which in L are stationary. Is there a similar such result for subsets of ω2L? Building on work of M. Stanley [9], we show that there is not. We shall also consider a number of related problems, examining the extent to which they are “solvable” in the above sense, as well as denning a notion of reduction between them.


2003 ◽  
Vol 68 (3) ◽  
pp. 837-845 ◽  
Author(s):  
John Krueger

AbstractWe strengthen a theorem of Gitik and Shelah [6] by showing that if κ is either weakly inaccessible or the successor of a singular cardinal and S is a stationary subset of κ such that NSκ↾S is saturated then κ ∖ S is fat. Using this theorem we derive some results about the existence of fat stationary sets. We then strengthen some results due to Baumgartner and Taylor [2], showing in particular that if I is a λ+++-saturated normal ideal on Pκλ then the conditions of being λ+-preserving, weakly presaturated, and presaturated are equivalent for I.


2003 ◽  
Vol 68 (2) ◽  
pp. 637-643 ◽  
Author(s):  
James Cummings ◽  
Matthew Foreman ◽  
Menachem Magidor

This note proves two theorems. The first is that it is consistent to have for every n, but not have . This is done by carefully collapsing a supercompact cardinal and adding square sequences to each ωn. The crux of the proof is that in the resulting model every stationary subset of ℵω+1 ⋂ cof(ω) reflects to an ordinal of cofinality ω1, that is to say it has stationary intersection with such an ordinal.This result contrasts with compactness properties of square shown in [3]. In that paper it is shown that if one has square at every ωn, then there is a square type sequence on the points of cofinality ωk, k > 1 in ℵω+1. In particular at points of cofinality greater than ω1 there is a strongly non-reflecting stationary set of points of countable cofinality.The second result answers a question of Džamonja, by showing that there can be no squarelike sequence above a supercompact cardinal, where “squarelike” means that one replaces the requirement that the cofinal sets be closed and unbounded by the requirement that they be stationary at all points of uncountable cofinality.


2002 ◽  
Vol 02 (01) ◽  
pp. 81-89 ◽  
Author(s):  
YO MATSUBARA ◽  
SAHARON SHELAH

We prove that if λ is a strong limit singular cardinal and κ a regular uncountable cardinal < λ, then NSκλ, the non-stationary ideal over [Formula: see text], is nowhere precipitous. We also show that under the same hypothesis every stationary subset of [Formula: see text] can be partitioned into λκ disjoint stationary sets.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document