scholarly journals No Relation for Wigner’s Friend

Author(s):  
Leonardo Castellani
Keyword(s):  
2020 ◽  
Vol 190 (12) ◽  
pp. 1335-1342
Author(s):  
Aleksandr V. Belinsky

2019 ◽  
Vol 5 (9) ◽  
pp. eaaw9832 ◽  
Author(s):  
Massimiliano Proietti ◽  
Alexander Pickston ◽  
Francesco Graffitti ◽  
Peter Barrow ◽  
Dmytro Kundys ◽  
...  

The scientific method relies on facts, established through repeated measurements and agreed upon universally, independently of who observed them. In quantum mechanics the objectivity of observations is not so clear, most markedly exposed in Wigner’s eponymous thought experiment where two observers can experience seemingly different realities. The question whether the observers’ narratives can be reconciled has only recently been made accessible to empirical investigation, through recent no-go theorems that construct an extended Wigner’s friend scenario with four observers. In a state-of-the-art six-photon experiment, we realize this extended Wigner’s friend scenario, experimentally violating the associated Bell-type inequality by five standard deviations. If one holds fast to the assumptions of locality and free choice, this result implies that quantum theory should be interpreted in an observer-dependent way.


Author(s):  
Robert Shuler

Background: Recently some photon models of a Wigner's friend experiment have led investigators to suggest objective reality does not exist, and to publish non-academic articles with such claims. The public is not equipped to evaluate the severe limitations of these experiments. The separation of Wigner from the experiment and use of only reversible coherent processes for the friend allow operations that are not possible in ordinary reality according to the latest quantum research. Methods: We suggest directly testing the implied claim that objective reality, including incoherent objects with irreversible non-destructive memory, can be held in superposition. We suspect it will fail, but provide for a graduated approach that may discover something about the conditions for superposition collapse. To this end we design a thought experiment to model the objective world, investigating under what conditions experimenters in the same world (ensemble member) will be able to record a result and find it does not appear to change. An observer has a viewing apparatus and a memory apparatus. A second uncorrelated viewer of the same recorded result is employed to obtain objectivity. By hypothesis the uncorrelated second viewer obtains the same view of the measurement record as the first observer. There are not two measurements. This is not an investigation of hidden variables. Results: To model the objective world, incoherent and irreversible processes must be included. To test for superposition, coherence has to be established. These seem to present a contradiction. Conclusions: The thought experiment has suggested new places to look other than size for the origin of objective reality from the quantum world, casts doubt on the Many-Worlds interpretation, and provides a method of testing it.


2020 ◽  
Vol 131 (4) ◽  
pp. 40001 ◽  
Author(s):  
A. Matzkin ◽  
D. Sokolovski
Keyword(s):  

2021 ◽  
Author(s):  
Satish Ramakrishna

Abstract The act of measurement on a quantum state is supposed to “decohere” and “collapse” the state into one of several eigenstates of the operator corresponding to the observable being measured. This measurement process is sometimes described as outside standard quantum-mechanical evolution and not calculable from Schr¨odinger’s equation [2]. Progress has, however, been made in studying this problem with two main calculation tools - one uses a time-independent Hamiltonian [18], while a rather more general approach proving that decoherence occurs under some generic conditions [21]. The two general approaches to the study of wave-function collapse are as follows. The first approach, called the “consistent” or “decoherent”’ histories approach [11], studies microscopic histories that diverge probabilistically and explains collapse as an event in our particular history. The other, referred to as the “environmental decoherence” approach[8, 21] studies the effect of the environment upon the quantum system, to explain wave-function decoherence. Then collapse is produced by irreversible effects of various sorts. In the “environmental decoherence” approach, one writes down a Markovian-approximated Master equation to study the time-evolution of the reduced density matrix and obtains the long-time dependence of the off-diagonal elements of this matrix. The calculation in this paper studies the evolution of a quantum system under the “environmental” approach, with a rather important analytic difference. We start from the Schr¨odinger equation for the state of the system, with a time-dependent Hamiltonian that reflects the actual microscopic interactions that are occurring. Then we systematically solve for the time-evolved state, without invoking a Markovian approximation when writing out the effective time-evolution equation, i.e., keeping the evolution unitary until the end. This approach is useful and it allows the system wave-function to explicitly “un-collapse” if the measurement apparatus is sufficiently small. However, in the limit of a macroscopic system, collapse is a temporary state that will simply take extremely long (of the order of multiple universe lifetimes) to reverse. While this has been attempted previously [12], we study a particularly simple and calculable example. We make some connections to the work by Linden et al [21] while doing so. The calculation in this paper has interesting implications for the interpretation of the Wigner’s friend experiment, as well as the Mott experiment, which is explored in Sections V and VI (especially the enumerated points in Section VI). The upshot is that as long as Wigner’s friend is macroscopically large (or uses a macroscopically large measuring instrument), no one needs to worry that Wigner would see something different from his friend. Indeed, Wigner’s friend does not even need to be conscious during the measurement that she conducts. In particular, as a result of the mathematical analysis, the short-time behavior of a collapsing system, at least the one considered in this paper, is not exponential. Instead, it is the usual Fermigolden rule result. The long-term behavior is, of course, still exponential. This is a second novel feature of the paper - we connect the short-term Fermi-golden rule (quadratic-in-time behavior) transition probability to the exponential long-time behavior of a collapsing wave-function in one continuous mathematical formulation.


Quantum ◽  
2021 ◽  
Vol 5 ◽  
pp. 524
Author(s):  
Veronika Baumann ◽  
Flavio Del Santo ◽  
Alexander R. H. Smith ◽  
Flaminia Giacomini ◽  
Esteban Castro-Ruiz ◽  
...  

The quantum measurement problem can be regarded as the tension between the two alternative dynamics prescribed by quantum mechanics: the unitary evolution of the wave function and the state-update rule (or "collapse") at the instant a measurement takes place. The notorious Wigner's friend gedankenexperiment constitutes the paradoxical scenario in which different observers (one of whom is observed by the other) describe one and the same interaction differently, one –the Friend– via state-update and the other –Wigner– unitarily. This can lead to Wigner and his friend assigning different probabilities to the outcome of the same subsequent measurement. In this paper, we apply the Page-Wootters mechanism (PWM) as a timeless description of Wigner's friend-like scenarios. We show that the standard rules to assign two-time conditional probabilities within the PWM need to be modified to deal with the Wigner's friend gedankenexperiment. We identify three main definitions of such modified rules to assign two-time conditional probabilities, all of which reduce to standard quantum theory for non-Wigner's friend scenarios. However, when applied to the Wigner's friend setup each rule assigns different conditional probabilities, potentially resolving the probability-assignment paradox in a different manner. Moreover, one rule imposes strict limits on when a joint probability distribution for the measurement outcomes of Wigner and his Friend is well-defined, which single out those cases where Wigner's measurement does not disturb the Friend's memory and such a probability has an operational meaning in terms of collectible statistics. Interestingly, the same limits guarantee that said measurement outcomes fulfill the consistency condition of the consistent histories framework.


2021 ◽  
Author(s):  
Szymon Łukaszyk

Abstract The Extended Wigner’s Friend thought experiment comprising a quantum system containing an agent who draws conclusions, upon observing the outcome of a measurement of a qubit prepared in two non-orthogonal versions by another agent led its authors to conclude that quantum theory cannot consistently describe the use of itself. It has also been proposed that this thought experiment is equivalent to coherent entangled state (Bell type) experiments. It is argued in this paper that the assumption of the freedom of choice of the first Wigner’s friend invalidates such equivalency. It is also argued that the assumption of locality (physical space) introduces superfluous identity of indiscernibles metric axiom, which is invalid in quantum domain and generally disproven by the Ugly duckling mathematical theorem.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document