scholarly journals Structural proof theory for first-order weak Kleene logics

2020 ◽  
Vol 30 (3) ◽  
pp. 272-289
Author(s):  
Andreas Fjellstad
Author(s):  
Sara Negri ◽  
Jan von Plato ◽  
Aarne Ranta

1988 ◽  
Vol 53 (2) ◽  
pp. 554-570 ◽  
Author(s):  
Kosta Došen ◽  
Peter Schroeder-Heister

This paper is meant to be a comment on Beth's definability theorem. In it we shall make the following points.Implicit definability as mentioned in Beth's theorem for first-order logic is a special case of a more general notion of uniqueness. If α is a nonlogical constant, Tα a set of sentences, α* an additional constant of the same syntactical category as α and Tα, a copy of Tα with α* instead of α, then for implicit definability of α in Tα one has, in the case of predicate constants, to derive α(x1,…,xn) ↔ α*(x1,…,xn) from Tα ∪ Tα*, and similarly for constants of other syntactical categories. For uniqueness one considers sets of schemata Sα and derivability from instances of Sα ∪ Sα* in the language with both α and α*, thus allowing mixing of α and α* not only in logical axioms and rules, but also in nonlogical assumptions. In the first case, but not necessarily in the second one, explicit definability follows. It is crucial for Beth's theorem that mixing of α and α* is allowed only inside logic, not outside. This topic will be treated in §1.Let the structural part of logic be understood roughly in the sense of Gentzen-style proof theory, i.e. as comprising only those rules which do not specifically involve logical constants. If we restrict mixing of α and α* to the structural part of logic which we shall specify precisely, we obtain a different notion of implicit definability for which we can demonstrate a general definability theorem, where a is not confined to the syntactical categories of nonlogical expressions of first-order logic. This definability theorem is a consequence of an equally general interpolation theorem. This topic will be treated in §§2, 3, and 4.


2020 ◽  
Author(s):  
Giorgi Japaridze

Abstract Cirquent calculus is a novel proof theory permitting component-sharing between logical expressions. Using it, the predecessor article ‘Elementary-base cirquent calculus I: Parallel and choice connectives’ built the sound and complete axiomatization $\textbf{CL16}$ of a propositional fragment of computability logic. The atoms of the language of $\textbf{CL16}$ represent elementary, i.e. moveless, games and the logical vocabulary consists of negation, parallel connectives and choice connectives. The present paper constructs the first-order version $\textbf{CL17}$ of $\textbf{CL16}$, also enjoying soundness and completeness. The language of $\textbf{CL17}$ augments that of $\textbf{CL16}$ by including choice quantifiers. Unlike classical predicate calculus, $\textbf{CL17}$ turns out to be decidable.


2015 ◽  
Vol 21 (2) ◽  
pp. 123-163 ◽  
Author(s):  
ROY DYCKHOFF ◽  
SARA NEGRI

AbstractThat every first-order theory has a coherent conservative extension is regarded by some as obvious, even trivial, and by others as not at all obvious, but instead remarkable and valuable; the result is in any case neither sufficiently well-known nor easily found in the literature. Various approaches to the result are presented and discussed in detail, including one inspired by a problem in the proof theory of intermediate logics that led us to the proof of the present paper. It can be seen as a modification of Skolem’s argument from 1920 for his “Normal Form” theorem. “Geometric” being the infinitary version of “coherent”, it is further shown that every infinitary first-order theory, suitably restricted, has a geometric conservative extension, hence the title. The results are applied to simplify methods used in reasoning in and about modal and intermediate logics. We include also a new algorithm to generate special coherent implications from an axiom, designed to preserve the structure of formulae with relatively little use of normal forms.


2002 ◽  
Vol 67 (1) ◽  
pp. 197-213 ◽  
Author(s):  
Robin Hirsch ◽  
Ian Hodkinson ◽  
Roger D. Maddux

AbstractWe confirm a conjecture, about neat embeddings of cylindric algebras, made in 1969 by J. D. Monk, and a later conjecture by Maddux about relation algebras obtained from cylindric algebras. These results in algebraic logic have the following consequence for predicate logic: for every finite cardinal α ≥ 3 there is a logically valid sentence X, in a first-order language ℒ with equality and exactly one nonlogical binary relation symbol E, such that X contains only 3 variables (each of which may occur arbitrarily many times), X has a proof containing exactly α + 1 variables, but X has no proof containing only α variables. This solves a problem posed by Tarski and Givant in 1987.


Author(s):  
Neil Tennant

This is a foundational work, written not just for philosophers of logic, but for logicians and foundationalists generally. Like Frege we seek to deal with the formal first-order language of mathematics. We revisit Gentzen’s proof theory in order to build relevance into proofs, while leaving intact all the logical power one is entitled to expect of a deductive logic for mathematics and for scientific method generally. Proof systems are constituted by particular choices of rules of inference. We raise the issue of the reflexive stability of any argument for a particular choice of logic as the ‘right’ logic. We examine the question of pluralism v. absolutism in choice of logic, and suggest that the informal notion of valid argument is stable and robust enough for us to be able to ‘get it right’ with our formal systems of proof for both constructive and non-constructive reasoning.


2006 ◽  
Vol 115 (2) ◽  
pp. 255-258
Author(s):  
H. T. Hodes

Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document