Theodore Hailperin. Foundations of probability in mathematical logic. Philosophy of science, vol. 4 (1937), pp. 125–150. See Corrections, ibid., p. 287.

1937 ◽  
Vol 2 (2) ◽  
pp. 95-96 ◽  
Author(s):  
Paul Henle

Bertrand Russell. My mental development. A reprint of IX 82(1). The philosophy of Bertrand Russell, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, second edition, The Library of Living Philosophers, Inc., Evanston, Illinois, 1946, pp. 1–20; also third edition, Tudor Publishing Company, New York 1951, pp. 1-20; also paper-bound reprint of the third edition, Harper Torchbooks, Harper & Row, Publishers, New York, Evanston, and London, 1963, Vol. I, pp. 1-20. - Hans Reichenbach. Bertrand Russell's logic. A reprint of IX 76(2). The philosophy of Bertrand Russell, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, second edition, The Library of Living Philosophers, Inc., Evanston, Illinois, 1946, pp. 21–54; also ibid. 1951, pp. 21-54; also ibid. 1963, Vol. I, pp. 21-54. - Morris Weitz. Analysis and the unity of Russell's philosophy. A reprint of IX 77(1). The philosophy of Bertrand Russell, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, second edition, The Library of Living Philosophers, Inc., Evanston, Illinois, 1946, pp. 55–121; also ibid. 1951, pp. 55-121; also ibid. 1963, Vol. I, pp. 55-121. - Kurt Göde. Russell's mathematical logic. A reprint of XI 75. The philosophy of Bertrand Russell, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, second edition, The Library of Living Philosophers, Inc., Evanston, Illinois, 1946, pp. 123–153; also ibid. 1951, pp. 123-153; also ibid. 1963, Vol. I, pp. 123-153. - James Feibleman. A reply to Bertrand Russell's introduction to the second edition of The principles of mathematics. A reprint of IX 77(2). The philosophy of Bertrand Russell, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, second edition, The Library of Living Philosophers, Inc., Evanston, Illinois, 1946, pp. 155–174; also ibid. 1951, pp. 155-174; also ibid. 1963, Vol. I, pp. 155-174. - G.E. Moore. Russell's “theory of descriptions.” A reprint of IX 78(1). The philosophy of Bertrand Russell, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, second edition, The Library of Living Philosophers, Inc., Evanston, Illinois, 1946, pp. 175–225; also ibid. 1951, pp. 175-225; also ibid. 1963, Vol. I, pp. 175-225. - Max Black. Russell's philosophy of language. A reprint of IX 78(2). The philosophy of Bertrand Russell, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, second edition, The Library of Living Philosophers, Inc., Evanston, Illinois, 1946, pp. 227–255; also ibid. 1951, pp. 227-255; also ibid. 1963, Vol. I, pp. 227-255. - Philip P. Wiener. Method in Russell's work on Leibniz. A reprint of IX 82(2). The philosophy of Bertrand Russell, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, second edition, The Library of Living Philosophers, Inc., Evanston, Illinois, 1946, pp. 257–276; also ibid. 1951, pp. 257-276; also ibid. 1963, Vol. I, pp. 257-276. - Ernest Nagel. Russell's philosophy of science. A reprint of IX 79. The philosophy of Bertrand Russell, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, second edition, The Library of Living Philosophers, Inc., Evanston, Illinois, 1946, pp. 317–349; also ibid. 1951, pp. 317-349; also ibid. 1963, Vol. I, pp. 317-349. - Andrew Paul Ushenko. Russell's critique of empiricism. A reprint of IX 80. The philosophy of Bertrand Russell, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, second edition, The Library of Living Philosophers, Inc., Evanston, Illinois, 1946, pp. 385–417; also ibid. 1951, pp. 385-417; also ibid. 1963, Vol. I, pp. 385-417.

1969 ◽  
Vol 34 (3) ◽  
pp. 495-496
Author(s):  
Ann S. Ferebee

Author(s):  
Roald Hoffmann

Implicit in the title might be two presumptions. The first one, that there is (or should be) a single philosophy of science, is not a claim I intend—I do think one should look for a common core, in a way that allows for differences. The second presumption, that philosophy of science, as it is construed today, would be different if it were based on chemistry, is what I wish to examine. And behind that latter supposition is the notion that philosophers of science, their professionalism and good will not impugned, nevertheless are likely to construct their worldview of science based on the sciences they know best. These are usually the sciences that they studied (a) as a part of their general education, or (b) the science they came from, so to speak, if they made their transition to philosophy at some later point in their career. I have not made a rigorous examination of the education of philosophers of science. But my anecdotal feeling is that, for those who entered the profession directly, an exposure to mathematical logic is more likely than to geology or chemistry. And, for many of the philosophers of science who came to their field after an initial scientific career, their scientific expertise was likely to be in the first instance physics, after that biology, and rarely chemistry. I will argue that this matters, for chemistry is different. There are exceptions. In the English-writing community, the most striking one is Michael Polanyi, a very distinguished physical chemist. In the French philosophical community, Pierre Duhem, Emile Meyerson, Gaston Bachelard, and Hélène Metzger had professional chemical backgrounds. Bernadette Bensaude-Vincent has argued convincingly that this background shaped their philosophical outlook, in contrast with the analytic philosophers of their time. In recent times the situation may have changed. A subfield of “philosophy of chemistry” has emerged, with annual meetings and two journals (Foundations of Chemistry, Hyle). The practitioners of this field are more likely to have had substantive experience in chemistry.


R. Dalbiez. L'idée fondamentale de la combinatoire leibnizienne. Travaux du IXe Congrès International de Philosophie, VI Logique et mathématiques, Actualités scientifiques et industrielles 535, Hermann et Cie, Paris1937, pp. 3–7. - Thomas Greenwood. L'extension de la logique aristotélicienne. Travaux du IXe Congrès International de Philosophie, VI Logique et mathématiques, Actualités scientifiques et industrielles 535, Hermann et Cie, Paris1937, pp. 18–25. - Z. Zawtrski. Importance des recherches logiques et sémantiques pour les théories de la physique contemporaine. Travaux du IXe Congrès International de Philosophie, VI Logique et mathématiques, Actualités scientifiques et industrielles 535, Hermann et Cie, Paris1937, pp. 82–87. - Paulette Février. Les relations d'incertitude d'Heisenberg et la logique. Travaux du IXe Congrès International de Philosophie, VI Logique et mathématiques, Actualités scientifiques et industrielles 535, Hermann et Cie, Paris1937, pp. 88–94. [Cf. II 88.] - R. Catesby Taliaferro. Plato and the liberal arts: a plea for mathematical logic. The new scholasticism, vol. 11 (1937), pp. 297–319. - Arnold F. Emch. Deducibility with respect to necessary and impossible propositions. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 2 (1937), pp. 78–81. - Garrett Birkhoff. Rings of sets. Duke mathematical journal, vol. 3 (1937), pp. 443–454. - N. H. McCoy and Deane Montgomery. A representation of generalized Boolean rings. Duke mathematical journal, vol. 3 (1937), pp. 455–459. - Gottfried Köthe. Die Theorie der Verbände, ein neuer Versuch zur Grundlegung der Algebra und der projektiven Geometrie. Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung, vol. 47 (1937), 1. Abteilung, pp. 125–144. - Adolf Fraenkel. Review of Carnap's Logische Syntax der Sprache (35212). Scripta mathematica, vol. 4 (1936), pp. 309–312. - A. P. Ushenko. Review of Carnap's The logical syntax of language. The philosophical review, vol. 46 (1937), pp. 549–553. - L. G. Review of Waismann's Einführung in das mathematische Denken (II 142). Rivista di filosofia, vol. 28 (1937), pp. 283–285. - Wilhelm Ackermann. Review of Bentley's Linguistic analysis of mathematics (4611). Jahrbuch über die Fortschritte der Mathematik, vol. 58I no. 1 (for 1932, pub. 1937), pp. 56–57. - C. G. Hempel. Review of Carnap's Die Antinomien und die Unvollständigkeit der Mathematik (35214). Jahrbuch über die Fortschritte der Mathematik, vol. 60II no. 1 (for 1934, pub. 1936), pp. 843–844. - Wilhelm Ackermann. Review of Quine's A system of logistic (4585). Jahrbuch über die Fortschritte der Mathematik, vol. 60II no. 1 (for 1934, pub. 1936), pp. 845–846. - C. G. Hempel. Review of Quine's Toward a calculus of concepts (I 111). Jahrbuch über die Fortschritte der Mathematik, vol. 62I no. 1 (1936), pp. 35–36. - Th. Skolem. Review of Tarski's Grundzüge des Systemenkalküls (28518, I 71). Jahrbuch über die Fortschritte der Mathematik, vol. 62I no. 1 (1936), pp. 38–39. - Friedrich Bachmann. Reviews of Gentzen's Die Widerspruchsfreiheit der Stufenlogik (I 119) and Die Widerspruchsfreiheit der reinen Zahlentheorie (I 75). Jahrbuch über die Fortschritte der Mathematik, vol. 62I no. 1 (1936), pp. 43–44. - M. Kokoszyńska. Filozofia nauki w Kole Wiedeńskim (Philosophy of science in the Circle of Vienna). Kwartalnik filozoficzny, vol. 13, pp. 151–165, 181–194. - M. Kokoszyńska. Review of Carnap's Testability and meaning (II 49). Kwartalnik filozoficzny, vol. 14, pp. 55–61. - M. Black. Review of Gonseth's Les mathématiques et la réalité (II 45). Mind, n.s. vol. 46 (1937), pp. 538–539. - Review of Carnap's Testability and meaning, part 2 (II 49). Mind, n.s. vol. 46 (1937), p. 546. - Edward Gleason Spaulding. A world of chance, or Whence, whither, and why. The Macmillan Company, New York, 1936, xxxiii+293 pp. - R. Feys. Notions de logistique. Mimeographed. 1st. edn., privately circulated, Brussels 1936, vi+102 pp. 2nd. edn., revised, on sale by the Revue Néoscolastique, Louvain 1937.

1937 ◽  
Vol 2 (4) ◽  
pp. 175-176

Author(s):  
Javier De Lorenzo ◽  
Andoni Ibarra

May 2020 marks the 25thanniversary of the death of Miguel Sánchez-Mazas, founder of Theoria - An International Journal of Theory, History and Foundations of Science and regarded as the person who brought mathematical logic to Spain. Here we present some of his biographical features, as well as a summary of his contributions, from his early work in the 1950s - introducing contemporary advances in logic and philosophy of science in a philosophically backward milieu dominated by the scholasticism of that era in Spain - to the development of a project of Lebnizian lineage aimed at producing an arithmetic calculation that would elude some of the difficulties confronting Leibniz's calculus.


1937 ◽  
Vol 4 (1) ◽  
pp. 125-150 ◽  
Author(s):  
Theodore Hailperin

Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document