scholarly journals Characterizing the upper set relation by general functionals

Keyword(s):  
2011 ◽  
Vol 5 (2) ◽  
pp. 90-93

ABSTRACT A Clinico-Radiological Study was conducted to establish a set relation between crest of residual alveolar ridge and neutral zone so that a uniform pattern could be followed for teeth setting. Thirty healthy edentulous patients with class – I ridge relation and who had not undergone any major oral surgical procedure was included in this study. Patients were divided into two groups, 1, who were edentulous from six months to two year and group 2, who were edentulous from two or more years. Fifteen patients were in each group. Results showed that in group 1 patients, neutral zone lied lingual to or on crest of alveolar ridge and in group 2 patients, neutral zone shifted to buccal side. Therefore, by studying the pattern of shift of neutral zone to buccal side we should come out with a reasonable plan for placing our teeth looking at duration of edentulousness.


2017 ◽  
Vol 152 (2) ◽  
pp. 107-122 ◽  
Author(s):  
Nazan Çakmak Polat ◽  
Gözde Yaylalı ◽  
Bekir Tanay
Keyword(s):  
Soft Set ◽  

1999 ◽  
Vol 64 (2) ◽  
pp. 575-589 ◽  
Author(s):  
Steven Givant

Tarski [19] proved the important theorem that the class of representable relation algebras is equationally axiomatizable. One of the key steps in his proof is showing that the class of (isomorphs of) simple set relation algebras—that is, algebras of binary relations with a unit of the form U × U for some non-empty set U —is universal, i.e., is axiomatizable by a set of universal sentences. In the same paper Tarski observed that the class of (isomorphs of) relation algebras constructed from groups (so-called group relation algebras) is also universal.We shall abstract the essential ingredients of Tarski's method (in Corollary 2.4), and then combine them with some observations about atom structures, to establish (in Theorem 2.6) a rather general method for showing that certain classes of simple relation algebras—and, more generally, certain classes of simple algebras in a discriminator variety V—are universal, and consequently that the collections of (isomorphs of) subdirect products of algebras in such classes form subvarieties of V. As applications of the method we show that two well-known classes of simple relation algebras, those constructed from projective geometries (sometimes called Lyndon algebras) and those constructed from modular lattices with a zero (sometimes called Maddux algebras), are universal. In the process we prove that these two classes consist precisely of all (isomorphs of) complex algebras over the respective geometries and modular lattices, provided that we choose the primitive notions of the latter structures in an appropriate fashion. We also derive Tarski's theorems and a related theorem of the author as easy corollaries of Theorem 2.6.


1999 ◽  
Vol 5 (3) ◽  
pp. 289-302 ◽  
Author(s):  
Gabriel Uzquiano

In [12], Ernst Zermelo described a succession of models for the axioms of set theory as initial segments of a cumulative hierarchy of levels UαVα. The recursive definition of the Vα's is:Thus, a little reflection on the axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (ZF) shows that Vω, the first transfinite level of the hierarchy, is a model of all the axioms of ZF with the exception of the axiom of infinity. And, in general, one finds that if κ is a strongly inaccessible ordinal, then Vκ is a model of all of the axioms of ZF. (For all these models, we take ∈ to be the standard element-set relation restricted to the members of the domain.) Doubtless, when cast as a first-order theory, ZF does not characterize the structures 〈Vκ,∈∩(Vκ×Vκ)〉 for κ a strongly inaccessible ordinal, by the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem. Still, one of the main achievements of [12] consisted in establishing that a characterization of these models can be attained when one ventures into second-order logic. For let second-order ZF be, as usual, the theory that results from ZF when the axiom schema of replacement is replaced by its second-order universal closure. Then, it is a remarkable result due to Zermelo that second-order ZF can only be satisfied in models of the form 〈Vκ,∈∩(Vκ×Vκ)〉 for κ a strongly inaccessible ordinal.


2009 ◽  
Vol 26 (4) ◽  
pp. 456-463 ◽  
Author(s):  
Maureen A. Sartor ◽  
Vasudeva Mahavisno ◽  
Venkateshwar G. Keshamouni ◽  
James Cavalcoli ◽  
Zachary Wright ◽  
...  

2016 ◽  
Vol 16 (02) ◽  
pp. 1660002 ◽  
Author(s):  
Paulo Varandas

In this paper, we study the mean return times to a given set for suspension flows. In the discrete time setting, this corresponds to the classical version of Kac’s lemma [11] that the mean of the first return time to a set with respect to the normalized probability measure is one. In the case of suspension flows we provide formulas to compute the mean return time. Positive measure sets on cross sections are also considered. In particular, this varies linearly with continuous reparametrizations of the flow and takes into account the mean escaping time from the original set. Relation with entropy and returns to positive measure sets on cross sections is also considered.


2011 ◽  
Vol 61 (3) ◽  
pp. 651-662 ◽  
Author(s):  
Hai-Long Yang ◽  
Zhi-Lian Guo
Keyword(s):  
Soft Set ◽  

2015 ◽  
Vol 146 (5) ◽  
pp. 259-262 ◽  
Author(s):  
Osamu Kaminuma ◽  
Minoru Gotoh ◽  
Akihiko Nakaya ◽  
Kimihiro Okubo ◽  
Takachika Hiroi

Author(s):  
Bekir TANAY ◽  
GÖZDE YAYLALI
Keyword(s):  
Soft Set ◽  

Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document