william ockham
Recently Published Documents


TOTAL DOCUMENTS

82
(FIVE YEARS 4)

H-INDEX

5
(FIVE YEARS 0)

Empiricisms ◽  
2020 ◽  
pp. 103-198
Author(s):  
Barry Allen

The empiricism of antiquity survived the scientific revolution and became a philosophy of modern science by forging an alliance with the new value of experiments, which did not exist (much) in antiquity. The experience that matters to empiricism is that from which we learn, and we have never learned so much from experience as after we began systematically to make experience experimental. The chapter profiles the rise of experimental philosophy in three phases. First, the European recovery of Aristotle, and early experiments with the logic of experiment in Robert Grosseteste and Roger Bacon. Second, transformation into the basic form that becomes modern empiricism in William Ockham and later nominalists. Finally, the emergence of modern experimental empiricism in Francis Bacon, Galileo, Boyle, and Newton. Along the way come reflections on the contributions of magic and alchemy to the emergence of experiments as a method of natural knowledge.


2020 ◽  
Vol 94 (2) ◽  
pp. 305-322
Author(s):  
Henrik Lagerlund ◽  

In this article, I present two virtually unknown sixteenth-century views of human freedom, that is, the views of Bartolomaeus de Usingen (1465–1532) and Jodocus Trutfetter (1460–1519) on the one hand and John Mair (1470–1550) on the other. Their views serve as a natural context and partial background to the more famous debate on human freedom between Martin Luther (1483–1556) and Erasmus of Rotterdam (1466–1536) from 1524–1526. Usingen and Trutfetter were Luther’s philosophy teachers in Erfurt. In a passage from Book III of John Mair’s commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics from 1530, he seems to defend a view of human freedom by which we can will evil for the sake of evil. Very few thinkers in the history of philosophy have defended such a view. The most famous medieval thinker to do so is William Ockham (1288–1347). To illustrate how radical this view is, I place him in the historical context of such thinkers as Plato, Augustine, Buridan, and Descartes.


2018 ◽  
Vol 29 (4) ◽  
pp. 409-423 ◽  
Author(s):  
Vesa Hirvonen

In their commentaries on the Sentences, Richard of Middleton, John Duns Scotus, William Ockham and Gabriel Biel reflect whether mentally-disturbed people can receive the sacraments (Baptism, Eucharist, confession, marriage) and fulfil juridical actions (make a will or take an oath). They consider that the main problem in ‘madmen’ in relation to the sacraments and legal actions is their lack of the use of reason. Scotus and Ockham especially are interested in the causes of mental disorders and the phenomena which happen in madmen’s minds and bodies. In considering mental disorders mostly as naturally caused psycho-physical phenomena, Scotus and Ockham join the rationalistic mental disorder tradition, which was to become dominant in the early modern era and later.


2018 ◽  
pp. 219-248
Author(s):  
MARILYN McCORD ADAMS
Keyword(s):  

Author(s):  
James M. Arcadi ◽  
Joshua R. Farris

Analytic theology (AT) is a particular approach to theology and the study of religion that engages with the tools, categories, and methodological concerns of analytic philosophy. As a named-entity, AT arrived on the academic scene with the 2009 Oxford University Press publication, Analytic Theology: New Essays in the Philosophy of Theology, edited by Oliver D. Crisp and Michael C. Rea. AT was arguably represented, prior to this publication, by the proto-analytic theologian Richard Swinburne in his noteworthy works on Christian doctrine (e.g. Providence and the Problem of Evil, Responsibility and Atonement, The Christian God, Faith and Reason, and The Resurrection of God Incarnate), as well as by other professional philosophers of religion such as Alvin Plantinga, Nicholas Wolterstorff, Richard Swinburne, William Alston, Eleonore Stump, Robert and Marilyn McCord Adams, Basil Mitchell, Keith Yandell, Paul Helm, and Stephen T. Davis, among others. These philosophers were addressing such topics as the coherence of theism, the rationality of religious belief, and the contributions of such philosophical theologians of the medieval past including Thomas Aquinas or William Ockham and those from modernity including René Descartes and Jonathan Edwards. Yet, the impetus for utilizing analytic philosophy to treat these topics emerged, not from the theological side of the conversation, but from the philosophical side. Anachronistically, then, the term “analytic theology” seems to aptly describe the work of these philosophers of religion.


2017 ◽  
Vol 19 (3) ◽  
pp. 25-44
Author(s):  
Rastislav Nemec
Keyword(s):  

Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document