Tense Logic Without Tense Operators

1996 ◽  
Vol 42 (1) ◽  
pp. 145-171 ◽  
Author(s):  
Frank Wolter
Keyword(s):  
Author(s):  
Quentin Smith

A special kind of logic is needed to represent the valid kinds of arguments involving tensed sentences. The first significant presentation of a tense logic appeared in Prior (1957). Sentential tense logic, in its simplest form, adds to classical sentential logic two tense operators, P and F. The basic idea is to analyse past and future tenses in terms of prefixes ‘It was true that’ and ‘It will be true that’, attached to present-tensed sentences. (Present-tensed sentences do not need present tense operators, since ‘It is true that Jane is walking’ is equivalent to ‘Jane is walking’.) Translating the symbols into English is merely a preliminary to a semantics for tense logic; we may translate ‘P’ as ‘it was true that’ but we still have the question of the meaning of ‘it was true that’. There are at least two versions of the tensed theory of time – the minimalist version and the maximalist version – that can be used for the interpretation of the tense logic symbols. The minimalist version implies that there are no past or future particulars, and thus no things or events that have properties of pastness or futurity. What exists are the things, with their properties and relations, that can be mentioned in certain present-tensed sentences. If ‘Jane is walking’ is true, then there is a thing, Jane, which possesses the property of walking. ‘Socrates was discoursing’, even if true, does not contain a name that refers to a past thing, Socrates, since there are no past things. The ontological commitments of past and future tensed sentences are merely to propositions, which are sentence-like abstract objects that are the meanings or senses of sentences. ‘Socrates was discoursing’ merely commits us to the proposition expressed by the sentence ‘It was true that Socrates is discoursing’. The maximalist tensed theory of time, by contrast, implies that there are past, present and future things and events; that past items possess the property of pastness, present items possess the property of presentness, and future items possess the property of being future. ‘Socrates was discoursing’ involves a reference to a past thing, Socrates, and implies that the event of Socrates discoursing has the property of being past.


2016 ◽  
Vol 46 (4-5) ◽  
pp. 735-758 ◽  
Author(s):  
Meghan Sullivan

AbstractA-theorists think there is a fundamental difference between the present and other times. This concern shows up in what kinds of properties they take to be instantiated, what objects they think exist and how they formalize their views. Nearly every contemporary A-theorist assumes that her metaphysics requires a tense logic – a logic with operators like (‘it was the case that...’) and (‘it will be the case that...’). In this paper, I show that there is at least one viable A-theory that does not require a logic with tense operators. And I will argue that three common indispensability arguments for tense operators are unsound.


Author(s):  
Dragana Sekulić

Does the definition of modality with the tense operators point to the thesis of universal determinism? Is the theorem about predetermination provable within the framework of tense logic and is with this the above-mentioned thesis proved also?Diodorus Kronos's main conclusion can be interpreted as an attempt to give an affirmative answer to the first question. Both analyses offered in this article show, however, that the determinism is presupposed in the premises of thia conclusion.The answer to the second question is somewhat more complex. This is discussed in the second part of the article.


Theoria ◽  
2008 ◽  
Vol 41 (3) ◽  
pp. 154-169 ◽  
Author(s):  
S. K. THOMASON
Keyword(s):  

Synthese ◽  
2015 ◽  
Vol 193 (11) ◽  
pp. 3677-3689 ◽  
Author(s):  
Patrick Blackburn ◽  
Klaus Frovin Jørgensen
Keyword(s):  

Author(s):  
Nicholas Rescher ◽  
Alasdair Urquhart
Keyword(s):  

Synthese ◽  
2015 ◽  
Vol 193 (11) ◽  
pp. 3639-3649
Author(s):  
Seiki Akama ◽  
Tetsuya Murai ◽  
Yasuo Kudo

Author(s):  
Peter Whiteford

Arthur Prior is scarcely a household name in New Zealand, but in some respects his story repeats a narrative we like to think of as quintessentially Kiwi—that of the small town boy who ‘makes it’ on the world stage. Born and raised in the rural township of Masterton in 1914, Prior became a leading philosopher of the 20th century, feted for his invention of tense logic (or temporal logic as it is now called), invited by no less a figure than Gilbert Ryle to deliver the prestigious John Locke lectures in Oxford in 1956, offered a Chair in Philosophy at Manchester in 1958, then a Fellowship at Balliol College, Oxford, in 1966. Tragically, he died at the relatively young age of 54, but he remains one of the central figures in the development of logic in the 20th century.


Author(s):  
Fei Liang ◽  
Zhe Lin

Implicative semi-lattices (also known as Brouwerian semi-lattices) are a generalization of Heyting algebras, and have been already well studied both from a logical and an algebraic perspective. In this paper, we consider the variety ISt of the expansions of implicative semi-lattices with tense modal operators, which are algebraic models of the disjunction-free fragment of intuitionistic tense logic. Using methods from algebraic proof theory, we show that the logic of tense implicative semi-lattices has the finite model property. Combining with the finite axiomatizability of the logic, it follows that the logic is decidable.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document