Studies in the History of Philosophy and Religion. Harry A. Wolfson , Isadore Twersky , George H. Williams

Speculum ◽  
1974 ◽  
Vol 49 (4) ◽  
pp. 776-777
1974 ◽  
Vol 34 (4) ◽  
pp. 601
Author(s):  
Daniel S. Robinson ◽  
Harry A. Wolfson ◽  
Isadora Twersky ◽  
George H. Williams

2021 ◽  
pp. 212-232
Author(s):  
Charly Coleman

This chapter presents Denis Diderot’s philosophy of the self in light of debates over the neuroscientific turn in historical research. Recent literature features an ideal of self-ownership that the history of philosophy shows to be radically contingent. Situating Diderot’s articles on dreaming and distraction in the Encyclopédie within the context of eighteenth-century theological and medical reflections on the self’s command over its ideas and actions, the chapter interrogates the relationship between science, philosophy, and religion. The dream state fascinated Diderot precisely because its structure and content allowed his contemporaries to reflect upon the fate of the human subject in a materially determined world.


2002 ◽  
Vol 23 (1-2) ◽  
pp. 1-15 ◽  
Author(s):  
Robert Bernasconi

Hegel is widely recognized as the preeminent philosopher of the history of philosophy. His Lectures on the History of Philosophy are designed in large measure to answer questions about philosophy's apparent futility by reformulating the presentation of the seemingly pointless succession of forms of philosophy so as to show its organic development (Hegel, 1994, 24). To reveal the proper shape of the history of philosophy, what is extraneous to it had to be omitted. Much that had previously been regarded as philosophy was now to be treated under the heading of religion. The distinction between philosophy and religion, the decision as to what was philosophy and what was religion, took on an importance it had previously lacked. Although subsequent historians of philosophy did not always share Hegel's concern to show the organic development of the history of philosophy, his decisions about what was to be included and what excluded from philosophy proved particularly important in respect of the question of the place subsequently given to Indian philosophy. For this reason Hegel deservedly holds a central place in current discussions about the philosophical canon.


Numen ◽  
1979 ◽  
Vol 26 (1) ◽  
pp. 112
Author(s):  
L. V. Berman ◽  
Harry A. Wolfson ◽  
Isadore Twersky ◽  
George H. Williams

Author(s):  
John Marenbon

‘Why medieval philosophy?’ considers why anyone should be bothered to learn about medieval philosophy. Very few people—philosophers and non-philosophers alike—do know much about this period of philosophy, but since it is now clear that there was a great deal of excellent philosophy written in the Middle Ages, is there not as much reason to learn about it as to learn about excellent philosophy from any other period? Medieval philosophy shows that the history of philosophy cannot be understood apart from the history of religions, not just because this is true for the time it covers, but because it points to how philosophy and religion were intertwined before then, and for long afterwards.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document