Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory Revisited

Keyword(s):  
2021 ◽  
pp. 48
Author(s):  
Aleksei V. Stovba

This article is a response to the criticism of Prof. O.V. Martyshin in the journal “State and Law” (2020. No. 12). The author has defended the thesis that there is no doubt as to whether the application of new terminology and philosophical methods of legal reasoning borrowed from contemporary philosophical trends and propagated by the representatives of the non-classical Philosophy of Law has brought positive results in Philosophy of Law and General legal theory.


Author(s):  
Linda Tvrdíková

If we look at the literature about judicial decision-making and interpretation of law, we can find many texts which are dedicated to legal arguments, logic and legal reasoning – in those texts the rationality, analytical and logical thinking is glorified and an interpretation seems ‘just’ as a logical operation where judges subsume certain facts under general legal norm or norms, those norms are formulated linguistically, so it seems that the whole job of judges is to analyze texts. What we can see more rarely are discussions and texts exploring the role of intuitions, feelings and emotions and their role in judicial decision-making – at least in the Czech Republic. Those of our faculties are seen as the source of bias and distortion. Even if we look to the past, those themes are not so common among legal theorists and philosophers – especially in our tradition where we are still influenced by Hans Kelsen and František Weyr and their normative theory – but we can find exceptions and those are the American legal realists. In this paper, we will show that their observations and insights seem to be right. How can we know it? Because in last decades cognitive scientists have made big progress in the area of decision-making and it seems that we are not so rational as we thought us to be. They have explored that our thinking does not take place only through the deliberative system but, surprisingly, there is also another one system which influences our decisions. This system is automatic, fast, and intuitive – some call this system S1, Seymour Epstein an experiential system. This automatic system is more influential than our deliberative system because it is always heard – we can use Jonathan Haidt’s metaphor of an elephant and a rider. S1, the intuitive, experiential system, is an elephant and S2, the deliberative, analytical system is the rider – in legal theory, we have talked about the rider a lot but we do not explore the elephant sufficiently. This paper will try to uncover the nature of the elephant.


1999 ◽  
Vol 18 (5) ◽  
pp. 537 ◽  
Author(s):  
Fernando Atria
Keyword(s):  

1979 ◽  
Vol 38 (2) ◽  
pp. 373-391 ◽  
Author(s):  
Laurence Goldstein

There can be no doubt that the existence of paradoxes has stimulated vigorous and highly productive activity in philosophy and in logic. Take two famous examples: The Liar Paradox, which arises from a sentence such asL This statement is false.and the Russell Paradox which arises from the sentenceR The class of all classes which are not members of themselvesis a member of itself.The first of these has been a source of anguish for over 2,000 years. The second has engaged the serious attention of logicians for over three quarters of a century. Investigation of paradoxes of this sort has spawned whole new fields of study, such as technical semantics and axiomatic set theory.It has been claimed that legal reasoning is infected with paradoxes and that these paradoxes are similar in structure to those, like the two we have cited, which are of interest to the logician. If this claim were true one of two consequences would follow. Either the jurisprudent would face what would in all likelihood be a protracted struggle with these legal paradoxes resulting, perhaps, in significant additions to legal theory, or else, if these paradoxes were sufficiently similar to those of the logician, he might try to utilise the logician's results to solve his own legal puzzles.The first alternative, though attractive to a theoretician, may appear rather dismal to those engaged in the business of law. Whereas reflection on the logical paradoxes can lead to only more refined abstractions—the philosopher's meat and drink—legal theory is rather intimately connected with practical affairs.


2016 ◽  
Vol 29 (3) ◽  
pp. 667-676 ◽  
Author(s):  
JOHN HASKELL

AbstractMartti Koskenniemi's From Apology to Utopia is (rightly) considered a classic in international legal theory. The study tracks the oscillation of international legal argument over hundreds of years to reconcile seeming incongruencies: legal reasoning does not provide determinacy, but it brings weighted direction to political conflict; legal categories are amorphous, yet also an autonomous field of study. Though not commonly engaged, the methodological and theoretical posture of the book is significantly informed by a theory of history. This article focuses on this historical element within the text as a means to analyze some of its central claims and situate it within a broader sociology of knowledge production particular to late twentieth century legal academia.


This volume provides a forum for some of the best new philosophical work on law, by both senior and junior scholars from around the world. The chapters range widely over issues in general jurisprudence (the nature of law, adjudication, and legal reasoning); the philosophical foundations of specific areas of law (from criminal law to evidence to international law); the history of legal philosophy; and related philosophical topics that illuminate the problems of legal theory.


Author(s):  
Iain Scobbie

This chapter initially examines philosophical approaches to the international use of force in an historical context before examining the development of the doctrine of collective security as the unifying value of international relations at the end of the First World War and subsequently. States’ right of self-defence is seen as an exception to this doctrine. Drawing on analytical legal theory and theories of legal reasoning, it explores the nature of an exception to a rule. This classification can be difficult to identify as legal propositions can compete rather than exist in a hierarchical rule-exception relationship. The parameters of self-defence as an exception to the doctrine of collective security and the prohibition on the use of force is explored in this light, casting doubt on the validity of contemporary attempts to expand self-defence to justify extra-territorial attacks on non-state actors within states deemed unwilling or unable to curb their hostile activity.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document