scholarly journals A Spurious Solution to a Genuine Problem: An In-Depth Look at the Import Drugs Act of 1848

2002 ◽  
Author(s):  
Angela Walch
Philosophy ◽  
2002 ◽  
Vol 77 (1) ◽  
pp. 67-86 ◽  
Author(s):  
Stephen J. Boulter

In this paper I offer a straight solution to Hume's problem of induction by defusing the assumptions on which it is based. I argue that Hume's problem only arises if we accept (i) that there is no necessity but logical necessity, or (ii) that it is unreasonable to believe that there is any form of necessity in addition to logical necessity. I show that Hume's arguments in favour of (i) and (ii) are unsound. I then offer a suggestion as to how the weakness of his arguments has escaped detection. Finally, having claimed that there remains a surmountable problem with inductive arguments, I end by characterising that problem and a possible approach to its solution.


2007 ◽  
Vol 76 (16) ◽  
Author(s):  
Ratko G. Veprek ◽  
Sebastian Steiger ◽  
Bernd Witzigmann

Philosophy ◽  
2015 ◽  
Author(s):  
Mary Leng

In the context of the philosophy of mathematics, the term “naturalism” has a number of uses, covering approaches that look to be fundamentally at odds with one another. In one use, the “natural” in naturalism is contrasted with non-natural, in the sense of supernatural; in this sense, naturalism in the philosophy of mathematics appears in opposition to Platonism (the view that mathematical truths are truths about a body of abstract mathematical objects). Naturalism thus construed takes seriously the epistemological challenge to Platonism presented by Paul Benacerraf in his paper “Mathematical Truth” (cited under Ontological Naturalism). Benacerraf points out that a view of mathematics as a body of truths about a realm of abstract objects appears to rule out any (non-mystical) account of how we, as physically located embodied beings, could come to know such truths. The naturalism that falls out of acceptance of Benacerraf’s challenge as presenting a genuine problem for our claims to be able to know truths about abstract mathematical objects is sometimes referred to as “ontological naturalism,” and suggests a physicalist ontology. In a second use, the “natural” in naturalism is a reference specifically to natural science and its methods. Naturalism here, sometimes called methodological naturalism, is the Quinean doctrine that philosophy is continuous with natural science. Quine and Putnam’s indispensability argument for the existence of mathematical objects places methodological naturalism in conflict with ontological naturalism, since it is argued that the success of our scientific theories confirms the existence of the abstract mathematical objects apparently referred to in formulating those theories, suggesting that methodological naturalism requires Platonism. A final use of “naturalism” in the philosophy of mathematics is distinctive to mathematics, and arises out of consideration of the proper extent of methodological naturalism. According to Quine’s naturalism, the natural sciences provide us with the proper methods of inquiry. But, as Penelope Maddy has noted, mathematics has its own internal methods and standards, which differ from the methods of the empirical sciences, and naturalistic respect for the methodologies of successful fields requires that we should accept those methods and standards. This places Maddy’s methodological naturalism in tension with the original Quinean version of the doctrine, because, Maddy argues, letting natural science be the sole source of confirmation for mathematical theories fails to respect the autonomy of mathematics.


1980 ◽  
Vol 10 (1) ◽  
pp. 21-45 ◽  
Author(s):  
Max Deutscher

Husser believed that Kant's great attempt to achieve and to understand the viewpoint of transcendental subjectivity failed. For “Kant, … so many presuppositions are ‘obviously’ valid, presuppositions which in the Humean sense are included in the world enigma (of how objectivity based on subjectivity is possible), (that he) never penetrated to the enigma itself.” The attempt failed in its origins, because Kant did not fully appreciate the character and extent of Hume's problem of the nature of the self and the possible extent of knowledge. Kant's attempt failed also in its results because Kant created mythical constructions; the noumenal object ‘behind’ sensible appearances, and the noumenal self ‘behind’ conscious describable acts and experiences. “Because he understands inner perception in this empiricist, psychological sense and because, warned by Hume's scepticism, he fears every recourse to the psychological as an absurd perversion of the genuine problem of the understanding, Kant gets involved in his mythical concept formation.”


1982 ◽  
Vol 29 (5) ◽  
pp. 8-12
Author(s):  
Rosalie Jensen ◽  
David R. O'Neil

Most children in the later primary grades and throughout the middle grades are functioning at the stage of concrete operations. When they are faced with genuine problem-solving situations they need concrete and pictorial aids, as well as guidance from adults in organizing information and choosing strategies.


2005 ◽  
Vol 12 (3) ◽  
pp. 136-143
Author(s):  
Larry E. Buschman

Principles and Standards for School Mathematics (NCTM 2000) recommends that classroom mathematics instruction be more problem- centered—children need to be given the opportunity to engage in genuine problem solving by answering questions to which the answer is not apparent or the solution method is not known in advance (Charles and Lester 1982; NCTM 2000). Traditionally, problem solving has been associated with routine word, or story, problems. However, almost any mathematical question can be a problem; even computational exercises can be problematic if the answer is not apparent and children have not been taught a solution method, such as a computational algorithm.


2010 ◽  
Vol 59 (1) ◽  
pp. 25-38 ◽  
Author(s):  
Trevor C Hartley

AbstractThis article considers the problem of ‘libel tourism’ (forum shopping in transnational libel cases) from the point of view of English and EU law (both relevant in certain situations). If proceedings are brought in a forum having no real connection with the case, and if the lex fori is applied, free speech in other countries could be undermined. This is particularly a problem where the case is brought in England, because of the pro-claimant slant of English libel law. The article notes when English conflicts law is applicable and when EU conflicts law is applicable, and explains the English and EU law regarding choice of law, jurisdiction and forum non conveniens in order to assess whether there is a genuine problem. It concludes that there is, particularly with regard to the Internet. Possible solutions are suggested.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document