Conditioned disjunction as a primitive connective for the erweiterter Aussagenkalkül

1953 ◽  
Vol 18 (1) ◽  
pp. 63-65
Author(s):  
Alan Rose

It has been shown that the conditioned disjunction function [X, Y, Z] with the same truth-table as (X & Y) ∨ (Z & ) together with the logical constants t and f, form a complete set of independent connectives for the 2-valued propositional calculus and that these connectives are self-dual. This has since been generalised to the theorem which states that the conditioned disjunction function [Y, X1, X2, …, Xm, Y] with the same truth-table as (X1 & J1(Y)) ∨ (X2 & J2(Y)) ∨ … ∨ (Xm & Jm(Y)) together with the logical constants 1, 2, …, m form a complete set of independent connectives for the m-valued propositional calculus and that these connectives are self-dual. It has been conjectured by Church that conditioned disjunction together with the universal and existential quantifiers form a complete set of independent connectives for the 2-valued erweiterter Aussagenkalkül. The object of the present paper is to prove a theorem for the m-valued erweiterter Aussagenkalkül which reduces, in the case m = 2, to the conjecture of Church. In the m-valued propositional calculus if the propositional variable X occurs as a free variable in the formula then (∃X) and (X) are read “there exists X such that ” and “for all X, ”, respectively. If for a given assignment of truth-values to the remaining free propositional variables occurring in , takes the truth-value f(x), where x is the truth-value of X, then (∃X) and (X) take the truth-values min (f(1), f(2), …, f(m)), max(f(1), f(2), …, f(m)), respectively. We shall prove:Theorem. The conditioned disjunction function, together with the universal and existential quantifiers, form a complete set of independent connectives for the m-valued erweiterter Aussagenkalkül.

1953 ◽  
Vol 49 (3) ◽  
pp. 367-376
Author(s):  
Alan Rose

In 1930 Łukasiewicz (3) developed an ℵ0-valued prepositional calculus with two primitives called implication and negation. The truth-values were all rational numbers satisfying 0 ≤ x ≤ 1, 1 being the designated truth-value. If the truth-values of P, Q, NP, CPQ are x, y, n(x), c(x, y) respectively, then


1986 ◽  
Vol 51 (2) ◽  
pp. 448-452 ◽  
Author(s):  
Masazumi Hanazawa ◽  
Mitio Takano

A many-valued logic version of the Craig-Lyndon interpolation theorem has been given by Gill [1] and Miyama [2]. The former dealt with three-valued logic and the latter generalized it to M-valued logic with M ≥ 3. The purpose of this paper is to improve the form of Miyama's version of the interpolation theorem. The system used in this paper is a many-valued analogue (Takahashi [4], Rousseau [3]) of Gentzen's logical calculus LK. Let T = {1,…, M} be the set of truth values. An M-tuple (Γ1,…, ΓM) of sets of formulas is called a sequent, which is regarded as valid if for any valuation (in canonical sense) there is a truth value μ Є T such that the set Γμ contains a formula of the value μ with respect to the valuation. (In the next section, and thereafter, we change the format of the sequent for typographical reasons.) Miyama's result is as follows (in representative form):(I) If a sequent ({A}, ∅,…, ∅, {B}) is valid, then there is a formula D such that(i) every predicate or propositional variable occurring in D occurs in A and B, and(ii) the sequents {{A}, ∅,…, ∅, {D}) and (D}, ∅,…, ∅, {B}) are both valid.What shall be proved in this paper is the following (in representative form):(II) If a sequent ({A1}, {A2}, …, {AM}) is valid, then there is a formula D such that(i) every predicate or propositional variable occurring in D occurs in at least two of the formulas A1,…, AM, and(ii) the following M sequents are valid:({A1},{D},…,{D}),({D},{A2},…,{D}),…,({D},{D},…,{AM}).Clearly the former can be obtained as a corollary of the latter.


1945 ◽  
Vol 10 (3) ◽  
pp. 61-82 ◽  
Author(s):  
J. B. Rosser ◽  
A. R. Turquette

In an m-valued propositional calculus, or a formalization of such a calculus, truth-value functions are allowed to take any truth-value t where 1 ≦ t ≦ m and m ≧ 2. In working with such calculi, or formalizations thereof, it has been decided to distinguish those truth-values which it is desirable for provable formulas to have from those which it is not desirable for provable formulas to have. The first class of truth-values is called designated and the second undesignated. This specification of certain of the m truth-values as designated and the remainder as undesignated is one of the distinguishing characteristics of m-valued propositional calculi, and it should be observed at the outset that two m-valued propositional calculi will be considered to differ even if they differ only in respect to the number of truth-values which are taken as designated.


2009 ◽  
Vol 74 (4) ◽  
pp. 1264-1272 ◽  
Author(s):  
David Diamondstone

AbstractA classical theorem in computability is that every promptly simple set can be cupped in the Turing degrees to some complete set by a low c.e. set. A related question due to A. Nies is whether every promptly simple set can be cupped by a superlow c.e. set, i.e. one whose Turing jump is truth-table reducible to the halting problem ∅′. A negative answer to this question is provided by giving an explicit construction of a promptly simple set that is not superlow cuppable. This problem relates to effective randomness and various lowness notions.


Author(s):  
FRANCESC ESTEVA ◽  
PERE GARCIA-CALVÉS ◽  
LLUÍS GODO

Within the many-valued approach for approximate reasoning, the aim of this paper is two-fold. First, to extend truth-values lattices to cope with the imprecision due to possible incompleteness of the available information. This is done by considering two bilattices of truth-value intervals corresponding to the so-called weak and strong truth orderings. Based on the use of interval bilattices, the second aim is to introduce what we call partial many-valued logics. The (partial) models of such logics may assign intervals of truth-values to formulas, and so they stand for representations of incomplete states of knowledge. Finally, the relation between partial and complete semantical entailment is studied, and it is provedtheir equivalence for a family of formulas, including the so-called free well formed formulas.


1998 ◽  
Vol 63 (4) ◽  
pp. 1201-1217
Author(s):  
Norman Feldman

In this paper we consider the three-valued logic used by Kleene [6] in the theory of partial recursive functions. This logic has three truth values: true (T), false (F), and undefined (U). One interpretation of U is as follows: Suppose we have two partially recursive predicates P(x) and Q(x) and we want to know the truth value of P(x) ∧ Q(x) for a particular x0. If x0 is in the domain of definition of both P and Q, then P(x0) ∧ Q(x0) is true if both P(x0) and Q(x0) are true, and false otherwise. But what if x0 is not in the domain of definition of P, but is in the domain of definition of Q? There are several choices, but the one chosen by Kleene is that if Q(X0) is false, then P(x0) ∧ Q(x0) is also false and if Q(X0) is true, then P(x0) ∧ Q(X0) is undefined.What arises is the question about knowledge of whether or not x0 is in the domain of definition of P. Is there an effective procedure to determine this? If not, then we can interpret U as being unknown. If there is an effective procedure, then our decision for the truth value for P(x) ∧ Q(x) is based on the knowledge that is not in the domain of definition of P. In this case, U can be interpreted as undefined. In either case, we base our truth value of P(x) ∧ Q(x) on the truth value of Q(X0).


1969 ◽  
Vol 62 (7) ◽  
pp. 553-556
Author(s):  
Margaret Wiscamb

In elementary logic the construction of truth tables, while not difficult, can be a long and tedious process. In this article I would like to present a simple graphic representation of the truth values of compound statements involving two or three components. The graph gives all the information found in a truth table and pictures the statement as an easily recognizable pattern. By using this graphing procedure, the simplifying of statements is shortened considerably. In fact, for statements involving only two components, with a little practice it can usually be done by inspection. Proving that a statement is a tautology becomes almost trivial.


2013 ◽  
Vol 427-429 ◽  
pp. 1917-1923
Author(s):  
Hong Lan Liu ◽  
De Zheng Zhang

The well formed formulas (wffs) in classical formal system of propositional calculus (CPC) are only some formal symbols, whose meanings are given by an interpretation. A probabilistic logic system, based on a probabilistic space, is an event semantics for CPC, in which set operations are the semantic interpretations for connectives, event functions are the semantic interpretations for wffs, the event (set) inclusion is the semantic interpretation for tautological implication, and the event equality = is the semantic interpretation for tautological equivalence. CPC is applicable to probabilistic propositions completely. Event calculus instead of truth value (probability) calculus can be performed in CPC because there arent truth value functions (operators) to interpret all connectives correctly.


2007 ◽  
Vol 15 (1) ◽  
pp. 115-137 ◽  
Author(s):  
Eros Corazza

After discussing some difficulties that contextualism and minimalism face, this paper presents a new account of the linguistic exploitation of context, situationalism. Unlike the former accounts, situationalism captures the idea that the main intuitions underlying the debate concern not the identity of propositions expressed but rather how truth-values are situation-dependent. The truth-value of an utterance depends on the situation in which the proposition expressed is evaluated. Hence, like in minimalism, the proposition expressed can be truth-evaluable without being enriched or expanded. Along with contextualism, it is argued that an utterance’s truth-value is context dependent. But, unlike contextualism and minimalism, situationalism embraces a form of relativism in so far as it maintains that semantic content must be evaluated vis-à-vis a given situation and, therefore, that a proposition cannot be said to be true/false eternally.


1936 ◽  
Vol 1 (1) ◽  
pp. 2-25 ◽  
Author(s):  
W. V. Quine

By concepts will be meant propositions (or truth-values), attributes (or classes), and relations of all degrees. The degree of a concept will be said to be 0, 1, or n (> 1), and the concept will be said to be medadic, monadic, or n-adic, according as the concept is a proposition, an attribute, or an n-adic relation. The common procedure in systematizing logistic is to treat these successive degrees as ultimately separate categories. The partition is not rested upon properties of the thus classified elements within the formal system, but is imposed rather at the metamathematical level, through stipulations as to what combinations of signs are to be accorded or denied meaning. Each function of the formal system is restricted, thus metamathematically, to one degree for its values and to one for each of its arguments. The theory of types imports a further scheme of infinite partition, imposed by metamathematical stipulations as to the relative types of admissible arguments of the several functions and stipulations as to the types of the values of the functions relative to the types of the arguments.The elaborateness of the metamathematical grillwork which thus underlies formal logistic accounts in part for the tendency of those interested in logistic less for the matters treated than for the structures exemplified to limit their attention to the propositional calculus and the Boolean calculus of attributes (or classes), which, taken separately, are independent of the partitioning. A second reason for the algebraic appeal of these departments is their freedom from bound (apparent) variables: for use of bound variables fuses systematic considerations with notational or metamathematical ones in a way which resists ordinary formulation in terms of fixed functions and their arguments. Freedom from bound variables may be regarded, indeed, as the feature distinguishing algebra from analysis.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document