On maximal theories

1991 ◽  
Vol 56 (3) ◽  
pp. 885-890 ◽  
Author(s):  
Zofia Adamowicz

Let S be a recursive theory. Let a theory T* consisting of Σ1 sentences be called maximal (with respect to S) if T* is maximal consistent with S, i.e. there is no Σ1 sentence consistent with T* + S which is not in T*.A maximal theory with respect to IΔ0 was considered by Wilkie and Paris in [WP] in connection with the end-extension problem.Let us recall that IΔ0 is the fragment of Peano arithmetic consisting of the finite collection of algebraic axioms PA− together with the induction scheme restricted to bounded formulas.The main open problem concerning the end-extendability of models of IΔ0 is the following:(*) Does every model of IΔ0 + BΣ1 have a proper end-extension to a model of IΔ0?Here BΣ1 is the following collection scheme:where φ runs over bounded formulas and may contain parameters.It is well known(see [KP]) that if I is a proper initial segment of a model M of IΔ0, then I satisfies IΔ0 + BΣ1.For a wide discussion of the problem (*) see [WP]. Wilkie and Paris construct in [WP] a model M of IΔ0 + BΣ1 which has no proper end-extension to a model of IΔ0 under the assumption IΔ0 ⊢¬Δ0H (see [WP] for an explanation of this assumption). Their model M is a model of a maximal theory T* where S = IΔ0.Moreover, T*, which is the set Σ1(M) of all Σ1 sentences true in M, is not codable in M.

1982 ◽  
Vol 47 (2) ◽  
pp. 416-422 ◽  
Author(s):  
L. A. S. Kirby

Flipping properties were introduced in set theory by Abramson, Harrington, Kleinberg and Zwicker [1]. Here we consider them in the context of arithmetic and link them with combinatorial properties of initial segments of nonstandard models studied in [3]. As a corollary we obtain independence resutls involving flipping properties.We follow the notation of the author and Paris in [3] and [2], and assume some knowledge of [3]. M will denote a countable nonstandard model of P (Peano arithmetic) and I will be a proper initial segment of M. We denote by N the standard model or the standard part of M. X ↑ I will mean that X is unbounded in I. If X ⊆ M is coded in M and M ≺ K, let X(K) be the subset of K coded in K by the element which codes X in M. So X(K) ⋂ M = X.Recall that M ≺IK (K is an I-extension of M) if M ≺ K and for some c∈K,In [3] regular and strong initial segments are defined, and among other things it is shown that I is regular if and only if there exists an I-extension of M.


2017 ◽  
Vol 10 (3) ◽  
pp. 455-480 ◽  
Author(s):  
BARTOSZ WCISŁO ◽  
MATEUSZ ŁEŁYK

AbstractWe prove that the theory of the extensional compositional truth predicate for the language of arithmetic with Δ0-induction scheme for the truth predicate and the full arithmetical induction scheme is not conservative over Peano Arithmetic. In addition, we show that a slightly modified theory of truth actually proves the global reflection principle over the base theory.


2006 ◽  
Vol 71 (1) ◽  
pp. 203-216 ◽  
Author(s):  
Ermek S. Nurkhaidarov

In this paper we study the automorphism groups of countable arithmetically saturated models of Peano Arithmetic. The automorphism groups of such structures form a rich class of permutation groups. When studying the automorphism group of a model, one is interested to what extent a model is recoverable from its automorphism group. Kossak-Schmerl [12] show that if M is a countable, arithmetically saturated model of Peano Arithmetic, then Aut(M) codes SSy(M). Using that result they prove:Let M1. M2 be countable arithmetically saturated models of Peano Arithmetic such that Aut(M1) ≅ Aut(M2). Then SSy(M1) = SSy(M2).We show that if M is a countable arithmetically saturated of Peano Arithmetic, then Aut(M) can recognize if some maximal open subgroup is a stabilizer of a nonstandard element, which is smaller than any nonstandard definable element. That fact is used to show the main theorem:Let M1, M2be countable arithmetically saturated models of Peano Arithmetic such that Aut(M1) ≅ Aut(M2). Then for every n < ωHere RT2n is Infinite Ramsey's Theorem stating that every 2-coloring of [ω]n has an infinite homogeneous set. Theorem 0.2 shows that for models of a false arithmetic the converse of Kossak-Schmerl Theorem 0.1 is not true. Using the results of Reverse Mathematics we obtain the following corollary:There exist four countable arithmetically saturated models of Peano Arithmetic such that they have the same standard system but their automorphism groups are pairwise non-isomorphic.


2014 ◽  
Vol 79 (2) ◽  
pp. 496-525 ◽  
Author(s):  
SAMUEL R. BUSS ◽  
LESZEK ALEKSANDER KOŁODZIEJCZYK ◽  
NEIL THAPEN

AbstractWe study the long-standing open problem of giving $\forall {\rm{\Sigma }}_1^b$ separations for fragments of bounded arithmetic in the relativized setting. Rather than considering the usual fragments defined by the amount of induction they allow, we study Jeřábek’s theories for approximate counting and their subtheories. We show that the $\forall {\rm{\Sigma }}_1^b$ Herbrandized ordering principle is unprovable in a fragment of bounded arithmetic that includes the injective weak pigeonhole principle for polynomial time functions, and also in a fragment that includes the surjective weak pigeonhole principle for FPNP functions. We further give new propositional translations, in terms of random resolution refutations, for the consequences of $T_2^1$ augmented with the surjective weak pigeonhole principle for polynomial time functions.


2018 ◽  
Vol 83 (1) ◽  
pp. 326-348 ◽  
Author(s):  
RUSSELL MILLER ◽  
BJORN POONEN ◽  
HANS SCHOUTENS ◽  
ALEXANDRA SHLAPENTOKH

AbstractFried and Kollár constructed a fully faithful functor from the category of graphs to the category of fields. We give a new construction of such a functor and use it to resolve a longstanding open problem in computable model theory, by showing that for every nontrivial countable structure${\cal S}$, there exists a countable field${\cal F}$of arbitrary characteristic with the same essential computable-model-theoretic properties as${\cal S}$. Along the way, we develop a new “computable category theory”, and prove that our functor and its partially defined inverse (restricted to the categories of countable graphs and countable fields) are computable functors.


1970 ◽  
Vol 22 (3) ◽  
pp. 569-581 ◽  
Author(s):  
S. K. Thomason

In this paper we shall prove that every finite lattice is isomorphic to a sublattice of the degrees of unsolvability, and that every one of a certain class of finite lattices is isomorphic to an initial segment of degrees.Acknowledgment. I am grateful to Ralph McKenzie for his assistance in matters of lattice theory.1. Representation of lattices. The equivalence lattice of the set S consists of all equivalence relations on S, ordered by setting θ ≦ θ’ if for all a and b in S, a θ b ⇒ a θ’ b. The least upper bound and greatest lower bound in are given by the ⋃ and ⋂ operations:


2016 ◽  
Vol 22 (2) ◽  
pp. 249-286 ◽  
Author(s):  
LAURENT BIENVENU ◽  
CHRISTOPHER P. PORTER

AbstractA set of infinite binary sequences ${\cal C} \subseteq 2$ℕ is negligible if there is no partial probabilistic algorithm that produces an element of this set with positive probability. The study of negligibility is of particular interest in the context of ${\rm{\Pi }}_1^0 $ classes. In this paper, we introduce the notion of depth for ${\rm{\Pi }}_1^0 $ classes, which is a stronger form of negligibility. Whereas a negligible ${\rm{\Pi }}_1^0 $ class ${\cal C}$ has the property that one cannot probabilistically compute a member of ${\cal C}$ with positive probability, a deep ${\rm{\Pi }}_1^0 $ class ${\cal C}$ has the property that one cannot probabilistically compute an initial segment of a member of ${\cal C}$ with high probability. That is, the probability of computing a length n initial segment of a deep ${\rm{\Pi }}_1^0 $ class converges to 0 effectively in n.We prove a number of basic results about depth, negligibility, and a variant of negligibility that we call tt-negligibility. We provide a number of examples of deep ${\rm{\Pi }}_1^0 $ classes that occur naturally in computability theory and algorithmic randomness. We also study deep classes in the context of mass problems, examine the relationship between deep classes and certain lowness notions in algorithmic randomness, and establish a relationship between members of deep classes and the amount of mutual information with Chaitin’s Ω.


1987 ◽  
Vol 102 (3) ◽  
pp. 553-559 ◽  
Author(s):  
M. Aslam Chaudhry ◽  
J. N. Pandey

AbstractLet D(R) be the Schwartz space of C∞ functions with compact support on R and let H(D) be the space of all C∞ functions defined on R for which every element is the Hilbert transform of an element in D(R), i.e.where the integral is defined in the Cauchy principal-value sense. Introducing an appropriate topology in H(D), Pandey [3] defined the Hilbert transform Hf of f ∈ (D(R))′ as an element of (H(D))′ by the relationand then with an appropriate interpretation he proved that.In this paper we give an intrinsic description of the space H(D) and its topology, thereby providing a solution to an open problem posed by Pandey ([4], p. 90).


2016 ◽  
Vol 81 (1) ◽  
pp. 316-325 ◽  
Author(s):  
HRISTO GANCHEV ◽  
ANDREA SORBI

AbstractUsing properties of${\cal K}$-pairs of sets, we show that every nonzero enumeration degreeabounds a nontrivial initial segment of enumeration degrees whose nonzero elements have all the same jump asa. Some consequences of this fact are derived, that hold in the local structure of the enumeration degrees, including: There is an initial segment of enumeration degrees, whose nonzero elements are all high; there is a nonsplitting high enumeration degree; every noncappable enumeration degree is high; every nonzero low enumeration degree can be capped by degrees of any possible local jump (i.e., any jump that can be realized by enumeration degrees of the local structure); every enumeration degree that bounds a nonzero element of strictly smaller jump, is bounding; every low enumeration degree below a non low enumeration degreeacan be capped belowa.


1956 ◽  
Vol 8 ◽  
pp. 184-191 ◽  
Author(s):  
W. B. Jurkat

Introduction. This paper deals with questions of the following type. Problem (A) : Let F(x) be the nth integral of a positive non-decreasing function for all large positive x, the problem is to find a function f(x), being the nth integral of a non-decreasing function for all x (— ∞ < x < ∞), with the propertyA.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document