scholarly journals The birth of kindness

2021 ◽  
Author(s):  
CARLO BARGHINI

Kin-selection is sheer nonsense, based on the false assumption that the gene for helping is a rare gene, whose chance to be shared can only be provided by kinship. The gene for helping is instead universally shared within and across species with altricial young, invented to foster the survival of offspring. As begging and helping are complementary behaviors, both triggered by oxitocin ( mesotocin for lungfishes, amphibians, reptiles, and birds) begging is usually a reliable sign of the possession of the gene for helping. This is why helping is rewarding and allofeeding is widely diffused. Hence we can even see a sea gull feeding a penguin. It is not a mistake: it is the selfish gene for helping that recognizes itself in a gaping beak, not in an arbitrary tag as a green beard (Dawkins). If we have surplus of food and don't have offspring to feed, we too, as a sea gull, strive to bypass obstacles to energy flow, looking for someone else to feed, if not other humans, at least a pet.

Author(s):  
Thomas N. Sherratt ◽  
David M. Wilkinson

An altruistic act is one in which an individual incurs a cost that results in a benefit to others. Giving money or time to those less fortunate than ourselves is one example, as is giving up one’s seat on a bus. At first, one might consider such behaviour hopelessly naive in a world in which natural selection seemingly rewards selfishness in the competitive struggle for existence. As the saying goes, ‘nice guys finish last’. Yet examples of apparent altruism are commonplace. Meerkats will spend hours in the baking sun keeping lookout for predators that might attack their colony mates. Vampire bats will regurgitate blood to feed their starving roost fellows, while baboons will take the time and effort to groom other baboons. Some individuals, such as honeybee workers, forego their own reproduction to help their queen and will even die in her defence. The common gut bacterium Escherichia coli commits suicide when it is infected by a bacteriophage, thereby protecting its clones from being infected. If helping incurs a cost, then surely an individual that accepts a cooperative act yet gives nothing in return would do better than cooperators? What, then, allows these cases of apparent altruism to persist? In his last presidential address to the Royal Society of London in November 2005, Robert M. May argued, ‘The most important unanswered question in evolutionary biology, and more generally in the social sciences, is how cooperative behaviour evolved and can be maintained’. In this chapter, we document a number of examples of cooperation in the natural world and ask how it is maintained despite the obvious evolutionary pressure to ‘cheat’. We will see that, while it is tempting to see societies as some form of higher organism, to fully understand cooperation, it helps to take a more reductionist view of the world, frequently a gene-centred perspective. Indeed, thinking about altruism has led to one of the greatest triumphs of the ‘selfish gene’ approach, namely the theory of kin selection. Ultimately, as the quote from Mandeville indicates, we will see that cooperation frequently arises simply out of pure self-interest—it just so happens that individuals (or, more precisely, genes) in the business of helping themselves sometimes help others.


Author(s):  
Douglas Allchin

Enough of the “selfish gene,” already. It was a clever mental game, once, to imagine that genes are the ultimate units of evolution. That organisms are no more than a gene’s way of making more genes. The concept fundamentally confuses levels in biology. It implies that genes can have intent and moral perspective. The anthropomorphism is grossly misleading. Even Richard Dawkins, who originally launched the concept, now seems to acknowledge as much. When the notion was introduced, sociobiology was also new, promoting an evolutionary and genetic view of behavior. It was all too easy to consider all behavior, like genes, as “selfish.” Explanations of cooperation, “altruism,” and social reproductive behavior were reduced to genes through the concepts of inclusive fitness and kin selection. The supremacy of the individual seemed to epitomize Darwinism. These perspectives thus gradually became entrenched, and now appear as fact in virtually every textbook: another sacred bovine? Recently, however, E. O. Wilson, the prominent founder and advocate of sociobiology, has renounced kin selection in explaining societies with a single reproductive individual. The idea was that genetic relatedness could explain why some individuals did not themselves reproduce but instead helped others, their kin, reproduce similar genes. Three decades of research have shown that many cooperative breeding societies (such as termites) do not exhibit the required genetic structure of haplodiploidy. Moreover, many species that do (including sawflies and horntails) are not social. The documented cases and the explanation do not align. Rather, the societies in question—from ants and honeybees to beetles, shrimp, and naked mole rats—all seem to have nests with restricted access, guarded by just a few individuals. The social cooperation seems just an “ordinary” adaptation to certain conditions. The striking reproductive structure, Wilson now contends, is an evolutionary consequence—not a cause—of the social organization. Wilson’s dramatic turnabout illustrates a wider shift in perspective. For decades William Hamilton’s notion of kin selection largely eclipsed Robert Trivers’s concept of reciprocity as an explanation for cooperation. While the former is commonly presented in educational contexts, the latter has been nearly always absent.


1999 ◽  
Author(s):  
Ed O'Keefe ◽  
Matt Berge

2020 ◽  
Vol 67 (4) ◽  
pp. 305
Author(s):  
Hong Fu ◽  
Huan Zhang ◽  
Liang He ◽  
Yongcui Sha ◽  
Kangshun Zhao ◽  
...  

Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document