The Right Thing To Do With the Wrong Thing

2012 ◽  
Vol 93 (4) ◽  
pp. 1025-1026 ◽  
Author(s):  
Eugene H. Blackstone
Keyword(s):  
Author(s):  
Tatiana Muzychuk ◽  
Igor Anokhov

The article is dedicated to studying the process of information perception by an individual. A hypothesis is suggested that the environment that surrounds an individual is full of different signals, which have na­tural, social or technogenic origin. Separate signals can turn into information, if the recipient is able of discerning these signals and perceives them on the physical, intellectual, emotional and axiological levels of information perception. Whereas the complex of signals which are indiscernible for an individual are external noise. The authors state that interpretation of a signal by individuals begins on the physical level of perception which is necessary to synchronize their activity with that of the source of the signal. After that the individual has to move to the axiological level of information perception in order to coordinate the notions and meanings with the source of the signal. Furthermore, the authors substantiate the possibility of revealing two components in the structure of the discerned signal: «The Right Thing» and «The Wrong Thing» as an inherent beginning of any process of perceiving the outside world by an individual. The suggested hypothesis is illustrated in the article by the example of two kinds of information message: a painting by A. Deyneka and a poem by A. Blok which are studied in terms of the proposed hypothesis about the existence of levels of information perception and the possibility of discerning two basic elements in them: «The Right Thing» and «The Wrong Thing». The results of the research can be applied to improve the process of communicating and perceiving information.


1993 ◽  
Vol 41 (3) ◽  
pp. 381-393 ◽  
Author(s):  
Lesley Jacobs

The belief that state welfare programmes are justified because they enable many people to do what they could not otherwise have done is attractive. This article examines the claim that this belief flows logically from a particular account of what it means to have a right to do something. This enabling model of rights holds that rights can be violated in two ways: by interfering with people doing something they have a right to do and depriving the right-holders of the resources actually needed to do what they have a right to do. Having certain rights to do things can justify state action designed to provide people with the resources that enable them to do what they could not otherwise have done. However attractive this model of rights might be, it is unable to accommodate the possibility that an individual can have the right to do something which is the morally wrong thing to do.


BMJ ◽  
2006 ◽  
Vol 332 (7537) ◽  
pp. 353-354 ◽  
Author(s):  
Jonathan Samet ◽  
Heather Wipfli ◽  
Rogelio Perez-Padilla ◽  
Derek Yach

Author(s):  
Per-Olof H. Wikström

This chapter analyses and explains acts of crimes as moral actions (i.e., actions guided by what is the right or wrong thing to do) within an analytical criminology framework. It outlines some common problems of current mainstream criminological theorizing and research, such as the lack of a shared definition of crime, the poor integration of knowledge about the role of people and places in crime causation, the frequent confusion of causes and correlates, and the lack of an adequate action theory, and proposes a more analytical criminology as the remedy. The chapter introduces Situational Action Theory (SAT), a general, dynamic, and mechanism-based theory about crime and its causes, designed to address these problems and provide a foundation for an analytical criminology. It concludes by briefly discussing main implications for the future direction of policy and prevention.


Philosophy ◽  
1988 ◽  
Vol 63 (243) ◽  
pp. 63-81 ◽  
Author(s):  
Colin Radford

Utilitarianism tells us that actions are morally right and good if and to the extent that they add to human happiness or diminish human unhappiness. And—or, perhaps, therefore—it also tells us that the best action a person can perform is that which of all the possible actions open to him is the one which makes the greatest positive difference to human happiness. Moreover, as everyone will also remember, utilitarianism further tries to tell us, perhaps intending it as a corollary of that first, main claim, that the motive for an action has nothing to do with its moral rightness or goodness. (This, of course, is just a philosopher's excessive and incorrect way of making the platitudinous point that one may do the wrong thing for the right reason and the right thing for the wrong reason.) But even if, as utilitarians, we accepted the dubious corollary, it would not follow, as many have thought, that utilitarians have no moral interest in motives. For unless, absurdly, a utilitarian believed either that there was never more than a fortuitous connection between on the one hand what we intended to do and on the other what we did and the consequences of what we did, or that, if there were such connections, we could not know of them, he must believe, as a moralist, that the best motive a person can have for performing an action is likely to be the desire to produce the happiest result. Indeed, utilitarians ought to be morally committed, it would seem, to trying to find out as much as they can about the consequences of our actions, e.g. what connections exist, if any, between how we raise children and what sort of adults they grow up to be.


The debate about whether moral responsibility has an epistemic condition has traditionally focused on whether and, if so, when moral ignorance can provide an excuse for wrong actions. This chapter takes up the question of moral responsibility for right actions. Its central claim is that whether an agent is morally responsible for her right action depends on whether she knows what the right thing is to do. The chapter’s argument for this appeals to considerations from the philosophy of action. It argues that moral knowledge matters to moral evaluations because it is a central ingredient in intentional action. Our knowledge of what the right and wrong thing is to do partly determines whether we do the right or wrong thing intentionally. Moral responsibility inherits its epistemic condition from the epistemic condition on intentional action.


2007 ◽  
Vol 12 (1) ◽  
pp. 113-133 ◽  
Author(s):  
Robert Hanna ◽  
A.W. Moore

According to Kant, being purely rational or purely reasonable and being autonomously free are one and the same thing. But how can this be so? How can my innate capacity for pure reason ever motivate me to do anything, whether the right thing or the wrong thing? What I will suggest is that the fundamental connection between reason and freedom, both for Kant and in reality, is preciselyour human biological life and spontaneity of the will, a conjunctive intrinsic structural property of our animal bodies, which essentially constitutes human personhood and rational agency. I say ‘suggest’ because, obviously, no proper argument for such a conclusion could ever be worked out in a short essay. I would nevertheless like to motivate my suggestion by way of a commentary on the second part of Adrian Moore's extremely rich and interesting recent book,Noble in Reason, Infinite in Faculty(henceforth,NIR).


2007 ◽  
Vol 25 (18_suppl) ◽  
pp. 6504-6504
Author(s):  
E. G. Rivarola ◽  
E. Gil Deza ◽  
A. Negro ◽  
E. Morgenfeld ◽  
D. Juarez ◽  
...  

6504 Background: “Errors can be prevented by designing systems that make it hard for people to do the wrong thing and easy for people to do the right thing” (To Err is Human: Building a Safer Health System - report from the Institute of Medicine- USA). The current paper was designed to evaluate, prospectively, the different types of prescription deviation from standards as well as the way they are worked out in the daily practice. Methods: Between October 2004 and December 2006, the Tx of 6611 patients ( pt) were progressively entered into a database and compared with the national and international Tx recommendations (Evidence Based Oncology). The deviations between actual and recommended Tx were classified in two groups: Type I, or deviation from “Gold standard” (Off label prescription, experimental treatments or application of translational research with no evidence of better results regarding survival and/or quality of life over a standard Tx) and Type II, or medical errors with high malpractice risk (misdiagnosis, or drug prescription error in dosage, administration or schedule). The deviation was then pointed out to the attending physician, and their response was catalogued as: “A” (Immediate Correction), ‘B‘ (Administrative appeal to determine the treatment) or “C” (Court appeal to determine the treatment). Results: Eight hundred and sixty two errors were identified in the 6611 pt (13%). Six hundred and forty four (74,7%) were Type I and 218 (25,3%) were Type II.. The physicians were more reluctant to recognize Type I than Type II deviations. The response to the deviations were the following: Type I, response A= 454 cases (71%), Type I, response B 184 cases (28%), Type I, response C: 6 cases (1%). Type II response A: 196 cases (90%), Type II response B: 22 cases (10%). Type II response C: 0. Conclusions: 1) The implementation of a treatment-supervision system is the first step towards providing safer health care in oncology. 2) The 644 Type I prescriptions deviation appear to increase in relation to diffusion of innovations, and their modification is more conflictive. However, 71% are corrected immediately. 3) The 218 Type II prescriptions deviation appear to be related with medical expertise, and their resolution is simpler (90 % with immediate correction). An exhaustive taxonomy of deviations will be presented. No significant financial relationships to disclose.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document