An Intuitionistic Theory of Types: Predicative Part

Author(s):  
Per Martin-Löf
Studia Logica ◽  
1976 ◽  
Vol 35 (4) ◽  
pp. 377-385 ◽  
Author(s):  
Sergio Bernini

1973 ◽  
Vol 38 (1) ◽  
pp. 86-92 ◽  
Author(s):  
Dov M. Gabbay

Let T be a set of axioms for a classical theory TC (e.g. abelian groups, linear order, unary function, algebraically closed fields, etc.). Suppose we regard T as a set of axioms for an intuitionistic theory TH (more precisely, we regard T as axioms in Heyting's predicate calculus HPC).Question. Is TH decidable (or, more generally, if X is any intermediate logic, is TX decidable)? In [1] we gave sufficient conditions for the undecidability of TH. These conditions depend on the formulas of T (different axiomatization of the same TC may give rise to different TH) and on the classical model theoretic properties of TC (the method did not work for model complete theories, e.g. those of the title of the paper). For details see [1]. In [2] we gave some decidability results for some theories: The problem of the decidability of theories TH for a classically model complete TC remained open. An undecidability result in this direction, for dense linear order was obtained by Smorynski [4]. The cases of algebraically closed fields and real closed fields and divisible abelian groups are treated in this paper. Other various decidability results of the intuitionistic theories were obtained by several authors, see [1], [2], [4] for details.One more remark before we start. There are several possible formulations for an intuitionistic theory of, e.g. fields, that correspond to several possible axiomatizations of the classical theory. Other formulations may be given in terms of the apartness relation, such as the one for fields given by Heyting [5]. The formulations that we consider here are of interest as these systems occur in intuitionistic mathematics. We hope that the present methods could be extended to the (more interesting) case of Heyting's systems [5].


1976 ◽  
Vol 9 (1-2) ◽  
pp. 157-186 ◽  
Author(s):  
D.H.J. de Jongh ◽  
C. Smorynski

2004 ◽  
Vol 69 (3) ◽  
pp. 790-798 ◽  
Author(s):  
Sergei Tupailo

Abstract.We prove here that the intuitionistic theory T0↾ + UMIDN. or even EETJ↾ + UMIDN, of Explicit Mathematics has the strength of –CA0. In Section 1 we give a double-negation translation for the classical second-order μ-calculus, which was shown in [Mö02] to have the strength of –CA0. In Section 2 we interpret the intuitionistic μ-calculus in the theory EETJ↾ + UMIDN. The question about the strength of monotone inductive definitions in T0 was asked by S. Feferman in 1982, and — assuming classical logic — was addressed by M. Rathjen.


2003 ◽  
Vol 46 (1-4) ◽  
pp. 59-68
Author(s):  
Radomir Djordjevic

The paper reviews phaenomenological influences on Russian philosophical thought. Before the bolyshevique revolution of 1917, Husserl's ideas had attracted the attention of many Russian theoreticians, and during the last two decades effects of this impact are closely investigated. First of all there were several philosophers under very direct influence of phenomenology: N. O. Lossky, the author of numerous books, in his work on logic; S. L. Frank, who had developed an intuitionistic theory of knowledge Gustav Spet, logician, aesthetician, linguist etc, who accepted Husserl's conceptions in his books on interpretation, philosophy of history and philosophy of language; Alexiy Lossev, who wrote some thirty books, and in his early period (works on ancient dialectics, philosophy of language and logics) was phenomenologically oriented; etc. Husserl's philosophy has traced or affected the ideas of several other Russian thinkers, so in USSR as in exile throughout Europe (for instance, Georges Gurvitch).


If programming is understood not as the writing of instructions for this or that computing machine but as the design of methods of computation that it is the computer’s duty to execute (a difference that Dijkstra has referred to as the difference between computer science and computing science), then it no longer seems possible to distinguish the discipline of programming from constructive mathematics. This explains why the intuitionistic theory of types (Martin-Lof 1975 In Logic Colloquium 1973 (ed. H. E. Rose & J. C. Shepherdson), pp. 73- 118. Amsterdam: North-Holland), which was originally developed as a symbolism for the precise codification of constructive mathematics, may equally well be viewed as a programming language. As such it provides a precise notation not only, like other programming languages, for the programs themselves but also for the tasks that the programs are supposed to perform. Moreover, the inference rules of the theory of types, which are again completely formal, appear as rules of correct program synthesis. Thus the correctness of a program written in the theory of types is proved formally at the same time as it is being synthesized.


1977 ◽  
Vol 42 (4) ◽  
pp. 530-544 ◽  
Author(s):  
C. Smorynski

The main purpose of this note is to present new semi-model-theoretic proofs of some axiomatization results. Principally, we prove the result of [van Dalen and Statman] on the axiomatization of the equality fragment of the intuitionistic theory of apartness by ω-fold stability axioms. Further examples are also discussed.The intuitionistic theories of equality and apartness are given by the following nonlogical axioms:EQ .AP .In AP, one can define a notion of equality by means of the abbreviation:.The corresponding interpretation of E Q in AP is not faithful — since equality is a negation, we have stability of equality:.The equality fragment of AP is axiomatized by a suitable generalization of the stability of equality. To state it, one first defines a sequence of partial apartness relations:.A simple induction shows, for all n,whence.


Studia Logica ◽  
1978 ◽  
Vol 37 (4) ◽  
pp. 341-347 ◽  
Author(s):  
Norbert Wendel

Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document