Existentially closed central extensions of locally finite p-groups

1986 ◽  
Vol 100 (2) ◽  
pp. 281-301 ◽  
Author(s):  
Felix Leinen ◽  
Richard E. Phillips

Throughout, p will be a fixed prime, and will denote the class of all locally finite p-groups. For a fixed Abelian p-group A, we letwhere ζ(P) denotes the centre of P. Notice that A is not a class in the usual group-theoretic sense, since it is not closed under isomorphisms.

2016 ◽  
Vol 81 (3) ◽  
pp. 1069-1086
Author(s):  
CHARLES C. PINTER

AbstractThe Stone representation theorem was a milestone for the understanding of Boolean algebras. From Stone’s theorem, every Boolean algebra is representable as a field of sets with a topological structure. By means of this, the structural elements of any Boolean algebra, as well as the relations between them, are represented geometrically and can be clearly visualized. It is no different for cylindric algebras: Suppose that ${\frak A}$ is a cylindric algebra and ${\cal S}$ is the Stone space of its Boolean part. (Among the elements of the Boolean part are the diagonal elements.) It is known that with nothing more than a family of equivalence relations on ${\cal S}$ to represent quantifiers, ${\cal S}$ represents the full cylindric structure just as the Stone space alone represents the Boolean structure. ${\cal S}$ with this structure is called a cylindric space.Many assertions about cylindric algebras can be stated in terms of elementary topological properties of ${\cal S}$. Moreover, points of ${\cal S}$ may be construed as models, and on that construal ${\cal S}$ is called a model space. Certain relations between points on this space turn out to be morphisms between models, and the space of models with these relations hints at the possibility of an “abstract” model theory. With these ideas, a point-set version of model theory is proposed, in the spirit of pointless topology or category theory, in which the central insight is to treat the semantic objects (models) homologously with the corresponding syntactic objects so they reside together in the same space.It is shown that there is a new, purely algebraic way of introducing constants in cylindric algebras, leading to a simplified proof of the representation theorem for locally finite cylindric algebras. Simple rich algebras emerge as homomorphic images of cylindric algebras. The topological version of this theorem is especially interesting: The Stone space of every locally finite cylindric algebra ${\frak A}$ can be partitioned into subspaces which are the Stone spaces of all the simple rich homomorphic images of ${\frak A}$. Each of these images completely determines a model of ${\frak A}$, and all denumerable models of ${\frak A}$ appear in this representation.The Stone space ${\cal S}$ of every cylindric algebra can likewise be partitioned into closed sets which are duals of all the types in ${\frak A}$. This fact yields new insights into miscellaneous results in the model theory of saturated models.


1999 ◽  
Vol 64 (3) ◽  
pp. 991-1027 ◽  
Author(s):  
Françoise Delon ◽  
Patrick Simonetta

AbstractAn Ax-Kochen-Ershov principle for intermediate structures between valued groups and valued fields.We will consider structures that we call valued B-groups and which are of the form 〈G, B, *, υ〉 where– G is an abelian group,– B is an ordered group,– υ is a valuation denned on G taking its values in B,– * is an action of B on G satisfying: ∀x ϵ G ∀ b ∈ B υ(x * b) = ν(x) · b.The analysis of Kaplanski for valued fields can be adapted to our context and allows us to formulate an Ax-Kochen-Ershov principle for valued B-groups: we axiomatise those which are in some sense existentially closed and also obtain many of their model-theoretical properties. Let us mention some applications:1. Assume that υ(x) = υ(nx) for every integer n ≠ 0 and x ϵ G, B is solvable and acts on G in such a way that, for the induced action, Z[B] ∖ {0} embeds in the automorphism group of G. Then 〈G, B, *, υ〉 is decidable if and only if B is decidable as an ordered group.2. Given a field k and an ordered group B, we consider the generalised power series field k((B)) endowed with its canonical valuation. We consider also the following structure:where k((B))+ is the additive group of k((B)), S is a unary predicate interpreting {Tb ∣ b ϵB}, and ×↾k((B))×S is the multiplication restricted to k((B)) × S, structure which is a reduct of the valued field k((B)) with its canonical cross section. Then our result implies that if B is solvable and decidable as an ordered group, then M is decidable.3. A valued B–group has a residual group and our Ax-Kochen-Ershov principle remains valid in the context of expansions of residual group and value group. In particular, by adding a residual order we obtain new examples of solvable ordered groups having a decidable theory.


2017 ◽  
Vol 82 (1) ◽  
pp. 208-223 ◽  
Author(s):  
GEMMA CAROTENUTO

AbstractGiven a metric space (X , d), equipped with a locally finite Borel measure, a measurable set $A \subseteq X$ is a density set if the points where A has density 1 are exactly the points of A. We study the topological complexity of the density sets of the real line with Lebesgue measure, with the tools—and from the point of view—of descriptive set theory. In this context a density set is always in $\Pi _3^0$. We single out a family of true $\Pi _3^0$ density sets, an example of true $\Sigma _2^0$ density set and finally one of true $\Pi _2^0$ density set.


2019 ◽  
Vol 84 (02) ◽  
pp. 750-780
Author(s):  
GABRIEL CONANT ◽  
ALEX KRUCKMAN

AbstractWe study the theory Tm,n of existentially closed incidence structures omitting the complete incidence structure Km,n, which can also be viewed as existentially closed Km,n-free bipartite graphs. In the case m = n = 2, this is the theory of existentially closed projective planes. We give an $\forall \exists$-axiomatization of Tm,n, show that Tm,n does not have a countable saturated model when m, n ≥ 2, and show that the existence of a prime model for T2,2 is equivalent to a longstanding open question about finite projective planes. Finally, we analyze model theoretic notions of complexity for Tm,n. We show that Tm,n is NSOP1, but not simple when m, n ≥ 2, and we show that Tm,n has weak elimination of imaginaries but not full elimination of imaginaries. These results rely on combinatorial characterizations of various notions of independence, including algebraic independence, Kim independence, and forking independence.


1970 ◽  
Vol 22 (2) ◽  
pp. 249-254 ◽  
Author(s):  
D. B. Coleman

Let R be a commutative ring with unity and let G be a group. The group ring RG is a free R-module having the elements of G as a basis, with multiplication induced byThe first theorem in this paper deals with idempotents in RG and improves a result of Connell. In the second section we consider the Jacobson radical of RG, and we prove a theorem about a class of algebras that includes RG when G is locally finite and R is an algebraically closed field of characteristic zero. The last theorem shows that if R is a field and G is a finite nilpotent group, then RG determines RP for every Sylow subgroup P of G, regardless of the characteristic of R.


2019 ◽  
Vol 85 (1) ◽  
pp. 199-223 ◽  
Author(s):  
DAOUD SINIORA ◽  
SŁAWOMIR SOLECKI

AbstractWe give strengthened versions of the Herwig–Lascar and Hodkinson–Otto extension theorems for partial automorphisms of finite structures. Such strengthenings yield several combinatorial and group-theoretic consequences for homogeneous structures. For instance, we establish a coherent form of the extension property for partial automorphisms for certain Fraïssé classes. We deduce from these results that the isometry group of the rational Urysohn space, the automorphism group of the Fraïssé limit of any Fraïssé class that is the class of all ${\cal F}$-free structures (in the Herwig–Lascar sense), and the automorphism group of any free homogeneous structure over a finite relational language all contain a dense locally finite subgroup. We also show that any free homogeneous structure admits ample generics.


1971 ◽  
Vol 4 (3) ◽  
pp. 431-432
Author(s):  
Sheila Oates Macdonald

One condition on D was omitted from the statement of Theorem B in the paper [1], namely that (and the corresponding condition in Theorem A). The proof of the theorem clearly requires that this be so and it is not difficult to see that such a D can always be chosen. However, Dr R.M. Bryant has pointed out that not only is the theorem true as it stands, but indeed the conditions can be relaxed slightly to allow D to be any group such that.


2010 ◽  
Vol 83 (1) ◽  
pp. 96-107
Author(s):  
BOUBAKARI IBRAHIMOU ◽  
OMER YAYENIE

AbstractIt is well known that if a convex hyperbolic polygon is constructed as a fundamental domain for a subgroup of SL(2,ℝ), then its translates by the group form a locally finite tessellation and its side-pairing transformations form a system of generators for the group. Such a hyperbolically convex fundamental domain for any discrete subgroup can be obtained by using Dirichlet’s and Ford’s polygon constructions. However, these two results are not well adapted for the actual construction of a hyperbolically convex fundamental domain due to their nature of construction. A third, and most important and practical, method of obtaining a fundamental domain is through the use of a right coset decomposition as described below. If Γ2 is a subgroup of Γ1 such that Γ1=Γ2⋅{L1,L2,…,Lm} and 𝔽 is the closure of a fundamental domain of the bigger group Γ1, then the set is a fundamental domain of Γ2. One can ask at this juncture, is it possible to choose the right coset suitably so that the set ℛ is a convex hyperbolic polygon? We will answer this question affirmatively for Hecke modular groups.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document