A NOTE ON THE ASYMPTOTIC PROBABILITIES OF EXISTENTIAL SECOND-ORDER MINIMAL GÖDEL SENTENCES WITH EQUALITY

1995 ◽  
Vol 06 (04) ◽  
pp. 339-351
Author(s):  
WIESŁAW SZWAST

The minimal Gödel class is the class of first-order prenex sentences whose quantifier prefix consists of two universal quantifiers followed by just one existential quantifier. We prove that asymptotic probabilities of existential second-order sentences, whose first-order part is in the minimal Gödel class, form a dense subset of the unit interval.

2015 ◽  
Vol 3 (2) ◽  
pp. 46
Author(s):  
Nirbhay Kumar Sinha

<p>In this paper, we normalised the second-order part of the Hamiltonian of the problem. The problem is generalised in the sense that fewer massive primary is supposed to be an oblate spheroid. By photogravitational we mean that both primaries are radiating. With the help of Mathematica, H<sub>2</sub> is normalised to H<sub>2</sub> = a<sub>1</sub>b<sub>1</sub>w<sub>1</sub> + a<sub>2</sub>b<sub>2</sub>w<sub>2</sub>. The resulting motion is composed of elliptic motion with a short period (2p/w<sub>1</sub>), completed by an oscillation along the z-axis with a short period (2p/w<sub>2</sub>).</p>


2004 ◽  
Vol 69 (1) ◽  
pp. 118-136 ◽  
Author(s):  
H. Jerome Keisler ◽  
Wafik Boulos Lotfallah

AbstractThis paper studies the expressive power that an extra first order quantifier adds to a fragment of monadic second order logic, extending the toolkit of Janin and Marcinkowski [JM01].We introduce an operation existsn (S) on properties S that says “there are n components having S”. We use this operation to show that under natural strictness conditions, adding a first order quantifier word u to the beginning of a prefix class V increases the expressive power monotonically in u. As a corollary, if the first order quantifiers are not already absorbed in V, then both the quantifier alternation hierarchy and the existential quantifier hierarchy in the positive first order closure of V are strict.We generalize and simplify methods from Marcinkowski [Mar99] to uncover limitations of the expressive power of an additional first order quantifier, and show that for a wide class of properties S, S cannot belong to the positive first order closure of a monadic prefix class W unless it already belongs to W.We introduce another operation alt(S) on properties which has the same relationship with the Circuit Value Problem as reach(S) (defined in [JM01]) has with the Directed Reachability Problem. We use alt(S) to show that Πn ⊈ FO(Σn), Σn ⊈ FO(∆n). and ∆n+1 ⊈ FOB(Σn), solving some open problems raised in [Mat98].


2018 ◽  
Vol 15 (2) ◽  
pp. 124
Author(s):  
Alberto Voltolini

In this paper I want to claim, first, that despite close similarities, noneism (as developed in both Routley 1980 and Priest 20162) and Crane’s (2013) psychological reductionism are different ontological doctrines. For unlike the latter, the former is ontologically committed to objects that are nonentities. Once one splits ontological from existential commitment, this claim, I guess, is rather uncontroversial. Second, however, I want to claim something more controversial; namely, that this ontological interpretation of noneism naturally makes noneism be nonstandardly read as a form of allism, to be however appropriately distinguished from Quinean allism in terms of the different scope of the overall ontological domain on which the only particular/existential quantifier that there is ranges. This may orient a noneist towards a syncretistic view of existence, according to which, appearances notwithstanding, existence as a whole is captured both by means of second-order and by means of first-order related notions.


2005 ◽  
Vol 70 (4) ◽  
pp. 1297-1324
Author(s):  
Saharon Shelah ◽  
Mor Doron

AbstractWe consider a family of finite universes. The second order existential quantifier Qℜ means for each U Є quantifying over a set of n(ℜ)-place relations isomorphic to a given relation. We define a natural partial order on such quantifiers called interpretability. We show that for every Qℜ, either Qℜ is interpretable by quantifying over subsets of U and one to one functions on U both of bounded order, or the logic L(Qℜ) (first order logic plus the quantifier Qℜ) is undecidable.


2012 ◽  
Vol 504-506 ◽  
pp. 261-266 ◽  
Author(s):  
Jean Guillaume Orliac ◽  
Adrien Charmetant ◽  
Fabrice Morestin ◽  
Philippe Boisse ◽  
Stephane Otin

In order to simulate 3D interlock composite reinforcement behavior in forming processes like Resin Transfer Molding (RTM), it is necessary to predict yarns positions in the fabric during the preforming stage of the process. The present paper deals about thick 3D interlock fabric forming simulation using a specific hexahedral semi-discrete finite elements simulation tool : Plast4. Using the virtual work principle, we distinguish the virtual internal work due to tensions in yarns from other internal virtual works. The part of material stiffness relative to yarns tension is described as "first order stiffness" by a 3D discrete beam model. The rest of the rigidities - like transverse compression, shear strains or friction between yarns - are depicted by a continuous quad-based discretization designated in our work as "second order stiffness". A combination of this "first order" discrete model and a continuous orthotropic hyperelastic "second order" material formulation will enables us to simulate interlock preforming process. Jointly to the simulation work, we also had to specify and perform experimental testing identification of material's parameters. Thoses parameters concern both parts of the model. A bilinear tension approach for the yarns discrete modelization and an orthotropic continuous material for the "second order" part.


1991 ◽  
Vol 56 (2) ◽  
pp. 427-438 ◽  
Author(s):  
Leszek Pacholski ◽  
WiesŁaw Szwast

In [9] and [10] P. Kolaitis and M. Vardi proved that the 0-1 law holds for the second-order existential sentences whose first-order parts are formulas of Bernays-Schonfinkel or Ackermann prefix classes. They also provided several examples of second-order formulas for which the 0-1 law does not hold, and noticed that the classification of second-order sentences for which the 0-1 law holds resembles the classification of decidable cases of first-order prenex sentences. The only cases they have not settled are the cases of Gödel classes with and without equality.In this paper we confirm the conjecture of Kolaitis and Vardi that the 0-1 law does not hold for the existential second-order sentences whose first-order part is in Gödel prenex form with equality. The proof we give is based on a modification of the example employed by W. Goldfarb [5] in his proof that, contrary to the Gödel claim [6], the class of Gödel prenex formulas with equality is undecidable.


Author(s):  
R. Geel

SynopsisThis paper deals with initial value problems in ℝ2 which are governed by a hyperbolic differential equation consisting of a nonlinear first order part and a linear second order part. The second order part of the differential operator contains a small factor ε and can therefore be considered as a perturbation of the nonlinear first order part of the operator.The existence of a solution u together with pointwise a priori estimates for this solution are established by applying a fixed point theorem for nonlinear operators in a Banach space.It is shown that the difference between the solution u and the solution w of the unperturbed nonlinear initial value problem (which follows from the original problem by putting ε = 0) is of order ε, uniformly in compact subsets of ℝ2 where w is sufficiently smooth.


1997 ◽  
Vol 36 (04/05) ◽  
pp. 315-318 ◽  
Author(s):  
K. Momose ◽  
K. Komiya ◽  
A. Uchiyama

Abstract:The relationship between chromatically modulated stimuli and visual evoked potentials (VEPs) was considered. VEPs of normal subjects elicited by chromatically modulated stimuli were measured under several color adaptations, and their binary kernels were estimated. Up to the second-order, binary kernels obtained from VEPs were so characteristic that the VEP-chromatic modulation system showed second-order nonlinearity. First-order binary kernels depended on the color of the stimulus and adaptation, whereas second-order kernels showed almost no difference. This result indicates that the waveforms of first-order binary kernels reflect perceived color (hue). This supports the suggestion that kernels of VEPs include color responses, and could be used as a probe with which to examine the color visual system.


2017 ◽  
Vol 9 (3) ◽  
pp. 17-30
Author(s):  
Kelly James Clark

In Branden Thornhill-Miller and Peter Millican’s challenging and provocative essay, we hear a considerably longer, more scholarly and less melodic rendition of John Lennon’s catchy tune—without religion, or at least without first-order supernaturalisms (the kinds of religion we find in the world), there’d be significantly less intra-group violence. First-order supernaturalist beliefs, as defined by Thornhill-Miller and Peter Millican (hereafter M&M), are “beliefs that claim unique authority for some particular religious tradition in preference to all others” (3). According to M&M, first-order supernaturalist beliefs are exclusivist, dogmatic, empirically unsupported, and irrational. Moreover, again according to M&M, we have perfectly natural explanations of the causes that underlie such beliefs (they seem to conceive of such natural explanations as debunking explanations). They then make a case for second-order supernaturalism, “which maintains that the universe in general, and the religious sensitivities of humanity in particular, have been formed by supernatural powers working through natural processes” (3). Second-order supernaturalism is a kind of theism, more closely akin to deism than, say, Christianity or Buddhism. It is, as such, universal (according to contemporary psychology of religion), empirically supported (according to philosophy in the form of the Fine-Tuning Argument), and beneficial (and so justified pragmatically). With respect to its pragmatic value, second-order supernaturalism, according to M&M, gets the good(s) of religion (cooperation, trust, etc) without its bad(s) (conflict and violence). Second-order supernaturalism is thus rational (and possibly true) and inconducive to violence. In this paper, I will examine just one small but important part of M&M’s argument: the claim that (first-order) religion is a primary motivator of violence and that its elimination would eliminate or curtail a great deal of violence in the world. Imagine, they say, no religion, too.Janusz Salamon offers a friendly extension or clarification of M&M’s second-order theism, one that I think, with emendations, has promise. He argues that the core of first-order religions, the belief that Ultimate Reality is the Ultimate Good (agatheism), is rational (agreeing that their particular claims are not) and, if widely conceded and endorsed by adherents of first-order religions, would reduce conflict in the world.While I favor the virtue of intellectual humility endorsed in both papers, I will argue contra M&M that (a) belief in first-order religion is not a primary motivator of conflict and violence (and so eliminating first-order religion won’t reduce violence). Second, partly contra Salamon, who I think is half right (but not half wrong), I will argue that (b) the religious resources for compassion can and should come from within both the particular (often exclusivist) and the universal (agatheistic) aspects of religious beliefs. Finally, I will argue that (c) both are guilty, as I am, of the philosopher’s obsession with belief. 


2009 ◽  
Vol 74 (1) ◽  
pp. 43-55 ◽  
Author(s):  
Dennis N. Kevill ◽  
Byoung-Chun Park ◽  
Jin Burm Kyong

The kinetics of nucleophilic substitution reactions of 1-(phenoxycarbonyl)pyridinium ions, prepared with the essentially non-nucleophilic/non-basic fluoroborate as the counterion, have been studied using up to 1.60 M methanol in acetonitrile as solvent and under solvolytic conditions in 2,2,2-trifluoroethan-1-ol (TFE) and its mixtures with water. Under the non- solvolytic conditions, the parent and three pyridine-ring-substituted derivatives were studied. Both second-order (first-order in methanol) and third-order (second-order in methanol) kinetic contributions were observed. In the solvolysis studies, since solvent ionizing power values were almost constant over the range of aqueous TFE studied, a Grunwald–Winstein equation treatment of the specific rates of solvolysis for the parent and the 4-methoxy derivative could be carried out in terms of variations in solvent nucleophilicity, and an appreciable sensitivity to changes in solvent nucleophilicity was found.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document