scholarly journals Roberts’ weak welfarism theorem: a minor correction

Author(s):  
Peter J. Hammond

AbstractRoberts’ “weak neutrality” or “weak welfarism” theorem concerns Sen social welfare functionals which are defined on an unrestricted domain of utility function profiles and satisfy independence of irrelevant alternatives, the Pareto condition, and a form of weak continuity. Roberts (Rev Econ Stud 47(2):421–439, 1980) claimed that the induced welfare ordering on social states has a one-way representation by a continuous, monotonic real-valued welfare function defined on the Euclidean space of interpersonal utility vectors—that is, an increase in this welfare function is sufficient, but may not be necessary, for social strict preference. A counter-example shows that weak continuity is insufficient; a minor strengthening to pairwise continuity is proposed instead and its sufficiency demonstrated.

1930 ◽  
Vol 3 (4) ◽  
pp. 555-562 ◽  
Author(s):  
L. H. Adams ◽  
R. E. Gibson

Abstract Although many of the elastic properties of rubber have been investigated with very interesting results, no measurements have been made, so far as we know, of its cubic compressibility at high pressures. Those measurements which have been made at low pressures yield results varying from 93×10−6 obtained by Clapeyron to an estimate of the order of the compressibility of bronze (about 1×10−6) given by Amagat. As the compressibility of rubber enters as a minor correction into most compressibility measurements at high pressures, it is very desirable to have a reliable estimate of its value. In this communication we propose to give the results of experimental determinations of the compressibility at 25° of three samples of rubber which were furnished to us by H. L. Curtis and A. H. Scott of the U. S. Bureau of Standards. The samples are described as follows: Sample A.—Hard rubber from panel made by the Goodrich Company. It is a rubber-sulfur compound containing no inorganic fillers. The total sulfur amounts to 27.4 per cent, of which 0.21 per cent, is free sulfur. The density is 1.149 at 27° C. Sample B.—A rubber-sulfur compound containing 90 per cent. smoked rubber and 10 per cent. sulfur and vulcanized 105 minutes at 300° F. Density = 0.990 at 25°. Sample C consists of pale crepe rubber 90.75 per cent., zinc oxide 5 per cent., sulfur 4 per cent., tetramethylthiuram disulfide 0.25 per cent. It was vulcanized for 30 minutes at 260° F. Density = 0.990 at 27°.


1988 ◽  
Vol 82 (4) ◽  
pp. 1231-1244 ◽  
Author(s):  
H. P. Young

Condcrcet's criterion states that an alternative that defeats every other by a simple majority is the socially optimal choice. Condorcet argued that if the object of voting is to determine the “best” decision for society but voters sometimes make mistakes in their judgments, then the majority alternative (if it exists) is statistically most likely to be the best choice. Strictly speaking, this claim is not true; in some situations Bordas rule gives a sharper estimate of the best alternative. Nevertheless, Condorcet did propose a novel and statistically correct rule for finding the most likely ranking of the alternatives. This procedure, which is sometimes known as “Kemeny's rule,” is the unique social welfare function that satisfies a variant of independence of irrelevant alternatives together with several other standard properties.


1984 ◽  
Vol 14 (2) ◽  
pp. 123-133 ◽  
Author(s):  
Axel Reich

AbstractA premium calculation principle π is called positively homogeneous if π(cX) = cπ(X) for all c > 0 and all random variables X. For all known principles it is shown that this condition is fulfilled if it is satisfied for two specific values of c only, say c = 2 and c = 3, and for only all two point random variables X. In the case of the Esscher principle one value of c suffices. In short this means that local homogeneity implies global homogeneity. From this it follows that in the case of the zero utility principle or Swiss premium calculation principle, the underlying utility function is of a very specific type.A very general theorem on premium calculation principles which satisfy a weak continuity condition, is added. Among others the proof uses Kroneckers Theorem on Diophantine Approximations.


2020 ◽  
Vol 31 (05) ◽  
pp. 2050035
Author(s):  
Yong Luo ◽  
Hongbing Qiu

By using the integral method, we prove a rigidity theorem for spacelike self-shrinkers in pseudo-Euclidean space under a minor growth condition in terms of the mean curvature and the second fundamental form, which generalizes Theorem 1.1 in [H. Q. Liu and Y. L. Xin, Some Results on Space-Like Self-Shrinkers, Acta Math. Sin. (Engl. Ser.) 32(1) (2016) 69–82].


2017 ◽  
Vol 107 (4) ◽  
pp. 1239-1263 ◽  
Author(s):  
Hiroki Nishimura ◽  
Efe A. Ok ◽  
John K.-H. Quah

We develop a version of Afriat's theorem that is applicable in a variety of choice environments beyond the setting of classical consumer theory. This allows us to devise tests for rationalizability in environments where the set of alternatives is not the positive orthant of a Euclidean space and where the rationalizing utility function is required to satisfy properties appropriate to that environment. We show that our results are applicable, amongst others, to choice data on lotteries, contingent consumption, and intertemporal consumption. (JEL D11, D81)


1940 ◽  
Vol 5 (4) ◽  
pp. 149-149
Author(s):  
J. C. C. McKinsey

The purpose of this note is to call attention to a minor error in Lewis and Langford's Symbolic logic. On page 221, in discussing the Tarski-Łukasiewicz three-valued logic, the authors make the following assertion: “Let T(p) be any proposition, involving only one element, whose analogue holds in the two-valued system; if T(p) does not hold in the Three-valued Calculus, then pC.T(p) and Np.C.T(p) both hold.”I shall show, by means of a counter-example, that this assertion is not true. Let T(p) be the sentence:It is then easily verified that T(0) = T(1) = 1, and that T(½) = 0. Thus T(p) holds in the two-valued calculus, but not in the three-valued calculus. On the other hand, pC.T(p) does not hold, since ½.CT(½) = ½C0 = ½; similarly, Np.C.T(p) does not hold, since N½.C.T(½) = ½C0 = ½.


Author(s):  
Robin Thomas

Wagner made the conjecture that given an infinite sequence G1, G2, … of finite graphs there are indices i < j such that Gi is a minor of Gj. (A graph is a minor of another if the first can be obtained by contraction from a subgraph of the second.) The importance of this conjecture is that it yields excluded minor theorems in graph theory, where by an excluded minor theorem we mean a result asserting that a graph possesses a specified property if and only if none of its minors belongs to a finite list of ‘forbidden minors’. A widely known example of an excluded minor theorem is Kuratowski's famous theorem on planar graphs; one of its formulations says that a graph is planar if and only if it has neither K5 nor K3, 3 as a minor. But several other excluded minor theorems have been discovered by now (see e.g. [7–9]).


2007 ◽  
pp. 47-52
Author(s):  
A. Valjarevic

Based on the relevant available data, the distributions of masses and apparent magnitudes of stars belonging to globular star clusters are simulated. The simulations are aimed at examining the influence of the mass-segregation phenomenon on the surface-density profile. It is found that a minor correction should be introduced in order to infer the profile of the surface density from that of the surface brightness. .


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document