In the Name of the Law: Ventriloquism and Juridical Matters

Author(s):  
François Cooren

Cooren here applies his model of ‘ventriloquism’ to law and to the performances of legal speech, which allows him to detect the slight shifts in agency so characteristic of legal argumentation, and which helps reveal the complexity and polyphony of the apparently homophonic judicial utterance. From the Latourian notion of distributed action and the structure of faire faire – a theorem that consistently earns a central place in Latour’s oeuvre, Cooren launches his study by problematising anew canonical givens such as the binaries of passivity/activity and autonomy/heteronomy. We must not forget that ventriloquism involves not only the ventriloquist’s manipulation of the puppet but also the puppet’s manipulation of the ventriloquist, insofar as the latter says things that she, quite frankly, would never say were the puppet not attached to her hand. It is this strange loop of action and passion, autonomy and heteronomy, animation and inanimation, that characterises not only the puppeteer’s performance but also the lawyer’s and the judge’s performances, and, indeed, the structure of communication in general. What, then, does it mean to speak in the name of the law? Without succumbing to the snares of spontaneous hypostatisation, Cooren argues, in contrast to numerous theorists, that the law indeed possesses a sort of agency of its own. A host of legal and non-legal beings (prior judgments, witness testimony, documents of all kinds, emotions like frustration and anger, balances of power, statutes, healthcare reform policies, duplicity, etc.) are figured and mobilised to say certain things in the saying of the law: they are voiced by lawyers and judges, of course, but they also lend their own voices to the latter, shaping the means through which the law may pass.

Author(s):  
Fawzieh Salem Mubarak Busboos

Family reform and judicial discretion of the judge to resolve family disputes are one of the most important ways to protect the continuity and cohesion of the family، Islam has given the family a central place in society and has given it great care in terms of its foundation on the requirements of religion as well as in terms of its continuity on a solid foundation of intimacy and compassion. Islam as a realistic religion didn't rule out exposing this family for a series of conflicts that threaten its stability. Therefore، Islam urged to reform between the spouses whenever there is a disagreement between them. Islam gave the judge a judicial discretion in resolving family disputes. Jordanian Personal Status Law didn't deviate from what is prescribed in Islamic jurisprudence، where the judge was given a judicial discretion in resolving family disputes، A judicial discretion is the freedom that left by the law to a judge either expressly or implicitly، This is in order to choose the most appropriate and the closest solution among other solutions. We have concluded that one of the most important factors for the success of the judge in reducing family disputes is providing appropriate conditions for effort and reform attempts.


Do not be concerned by its appearance of complexity. It is a clear, manageable system of notation. The best understanding of this method can be obtained from briefly discussing it from three perspectives: 1 The original Wigmore Chart Method dating from 1913. 2 Anderson and Twining’s modification of the Wigmore Chart Method, from the mid-1980s. 3 Use of the modified method in this book as an aid for understanding argument construction. This will give a firm understanding of the discussions above through a practical demonstration. This discussion will then be followed by a practical demonstration of the modified Chart Method (changed slightly for our use) looking at the fictional criminal case of R v Mary. This is a demonstration devised to continue the development of argumentative skills already discussed in this chapter. A second case, R v Jack, is provided at the end of the chapter to allow students to try out their developing skills by analysing and charting a new case and building an argument. 7.10.1 The original Wigmore Chart Method John Wigmore wanted to restore an imbalance in the approach to evidence to be used in the trial. He first unveiled his views in an article published in the Illinois Law Review in 1913. He was concerned with issues surrounding the law of evidence. The law of evidence, as it is normally considered in university courses and in practice, is particularly concerned with the what type of evidence is admissible in court to prove the case of the parties. It is also concerned with the procedures that need to be followed to ensure that allowable evidence is not rendered inadmissible due to procedural and avoidable mistakes by those dealing with it before it reaches the court room. (This covers the field of forensic science as well as witness testimony.) Wigmore, however, believed that while the admissibility of evidence and the following of procedures are important aspects of the law relating to evidence, there was another more important area that had been completely ignored. This was the aspect of proof itself. What is the effect of the admissible evidence? How does it build to a finding of case proved for or against one party? Can it be said that there is a science of proof? Here of course issues relating to evidence and the construction of argument begin to merge. Wigmore sees proof in terms of the proving of points in argument persuading judges and juries of the outcome of a case. He argued:

2012 ◽  
pp. 240-240

1991 ◽  
Vol 1 (4) ◽  
pp. 281-293 ◽  
Author(s):  
Anita K. Barry

Abstract This article is concerned with the relationship between a witness' narrative style and judgments of jurors based on that style. It takes as its starting point the Duke University Law and Language Project results that a witness using a narrative style is judged more credible than a witness using a fragmented style. The main argument of this article is that it is not the use of narrative per se, but rather a particular narrative style that is valued in the courtroom. Data from a day of testimony in a murder trial is used to demonstrate two opposing narrative styles in testimony: that of the law enforcement officer and that of some nonexpert witnesses. It is shown first that the style of the law enforcement officers differs from ordinary conversation in its extreme explicitness. It is hypothesized that jurors will associate this style of delivery with credibility. It is further hypothe-sized that witnesses will lose credibility to the extent that they deviate from this style. After demonstrating the differences in the styles, the article draws on experimental work of other researchers to suggest that trial outcomes can be affected by the narrative style of the witness. (Linguistics)


2011 ◽  
Vol 6 (1) ◽  
Author(s):  
Giovanni Damele

Legal argumentation is usually considered the more formal (or, at least, formalistic) kind of practical argumentation, thanks to the long tradition of “legal syllogism” as its formal instrument, but also to its legal restraint (the formalistic aspect). Yet, in arguments such as those used, for example, by high courts in their justifications, we may find not only strict formalism and adherence to the letter of the law, but also the attempt to resolve differences of opinion and conflicts of interest, and perhaps also the rhetorical attempt to persuade the legal community, the legislator or even public opinion of the soundness of the court’s decision. But there could be more than that.


2019 ◽  
Vol 3 (2) ◽  
pp. 157-193
Author(s):  
Roberta Simões Nascimento

RESUMO:Uma das principais críticas que a teoria standard da argumentação jurídica recebe é falta de atenção dada às práticas legislativas. O momento da produção do direito é relevante? Como seria possível analisar uma argumentação legislativa? Como avaliá-la? Qual é o peso dos argumentos para o produto final, a lei? Na Espanha, Manuel Atienza, um dos primeiros autores a dar atenção ao tema, desenvolveu uma teoria da legislação que, com o passar o tempo, recebeu os elementos tendentes à formação do que se pode considerar a primeira teoria da argumentação legislativa. Para isso, o autor formulou cinco níveis ideais de racionalidade a serem alcançados pelas leis: (R1) racionalidade linguística ou comunicativa; (R2) racionalidade jurídico-formal ou sistemática, (R3) racionalidade pragmática, (R4) racionalidade teleológica, e (R5) racionalidade ética. Depois, acrescentou um nível transversal de meta-racionalidade: a razoabilidade. Em seguida, cruzou com as concepções formal, material e pragmática que marcam a sua teoria da argumentação jurídica. O objetivo do artigo é o de apresentar os desenvolvimentos teóricos de Manuel Atienza quanto à temática aos longo dos quase trinta anos em que vem estudando o tema, explicando os pontos fortes e as deficiências de sua teoria. Ao final, o presente trabalho propõe o aprofundamento de uma agenda de estudos mais ampla – a partir das ideias de Manuel Atienza e em resposta às críticas frequentemente lançadas à temática –, voltada para a promoção do giro argumentativo dentro do Poder Legislativo, fomentando a cultura de legisladores argumentadores, bem como apontando outros elementos na análise e avaliação das decisões legislativas e das argumentações respectivas, o que poderá resultar na construção de leis mais racionais. ABSTRACT:One of the main criticisms that the standard theory of legal argumentation receives is the lack of attention given to legislative practices. Is the law-making moment relevant? How can a legislative reasoning be analysed? How to evaluate it? What is the weight of the arguments for the final product, the parliamentary laws? In Spain, Manuel Atienza, one of the first authors to give attention to the subject, developed a theory of legislation that, over time, received elements tending to build what can be considered the first theory of legislative reasoning. For that purpose, the author formulated five ideal levels of rationality to be achieved by the laws: (1) linguistic or communicative rationality, (R2) legal-formal or systematic rationality, (R3) pragmatic rationality, (R4) teleological rationality, and (R5) ethical rationality. Then he added a transversal level of meta-rationality: the reasonableness. After that, he crossed with the formal, material and pragmatic conceptions that mark his theory of legal argumentation. The purpose of this article is to present the theoretical developments made by Manuel Atienza on this subject during the almost thirty years he has been studying it, explaining the strengths and weaknesses of his theory. In the end, this paper proposes to deepen a broader study agenda – based on Manuel Atienza’s ideas and in response to the criticisms frequently made on the subject – aimed at promoting the argumentative turn in the Legislative Power, fomenting culture of argumentative legislators, as well as pointing out other elements in the analysis and evaluation of legislative decisions and their respective arguments, which may result in the construction of more rational parliamentary laws.


2004 ◽  
Vol 14 (1-2) ◽  
pp. 1-38
Author(s):  
Suheil Bushrui

This essay offers a perspective on the state of the academy. It attempts to address reforms essential to the progress and development of society: retrieving the central place of teaching in the curriculum, inculcating humility in place of intellectual arrogance, protecting the academy against the intrusion of corporate and political agendas, abrogating the law of “publish or perish,” and finally, widening the intellectual and spiritual horizon of students by introducing them to the noble monuments of classical culture and to that “universal and unanimous tradition” represented in the spiritual heritage of the human race.


2021 ◽  
Vol 1(162) ◽  
pp. 59-81
Author(s):  
Grzegorz Maroń

The article approximates and critically assesses the philosophical and legal argumentation of deputies contained in their speeches at the sittings of the Sejm of the Republic of Poland of the 8th term (2015–2019). It discusses cases where parliamentarians, among other things, referred to the assumptions of particular philosophical-legal schools; commented on the essence, fea- tures, goals and values of law; argued about the optimal degree of positivisation of moral norms; quoted philosophers. The study revealed the in uence of the party a liation of MPs on their philosophical and legal argumentation. Deputies of the Law and Justice Party more often than others referred in their speeches to the axiology of law and natural law, emphasized the importance of justice and equity in the process of enacting and applying the law, and under- lined the role of social legitimacy of normative acts and court rulings. On the other hand, MPs belonging to the parliamentary opposition — especially the Civic Platform and the Modern Party members — highlighted the formal rule of law, opposed bills perceived as moralistic and confessional, and sought in justice and equity as the criteria for judgements the sources of excessive judicial discretion that threatened legal certainty and security. In the author’s view, the broadly understood philosophy of law has a utilitarian value for the parliamentary debate. It is desirable, however, that MPs’ remarks of a philosophical and legal nature should be part of factual argumentation, and not reduced to super cial rhetoric or linguistic ornamentation.


2018 ◽  
Author(s):  
Fransiska Novita Eleanora

legal argumentation is reasoning about the law or basic search of how a judges the case/case law, a lawyer to argue the law and how a legal expert to reason about the law. The method is bibliography study, result is because the purpose of writing to find out how the application of legal arguments in the community. The result is the application in society must not conflicts with the values and of the life in society.


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document