Physics and Metaphysics in Descartes and Newton

Author(s):  
Andrew Janiak

Isaac Newton had a vexed relationship with his most important immediate predecessor in mathematics and philosophy, René Descartes. He was typically loath to admit the importance of Cartesian ideas for the development of his own thinking in mathematics and natural philosophy. For this reason, generations of students and scholars relying on Newton’s published work had little inkling of Descartes’s significance. This unfortunate fact was compounded by the tendency of philosophers to focus on the Meditations or the Regulae in their scholarship, for it was Descartes’s Principles above all that influenced Newton’s thinking as a young man. With the discovery of a previously unpublished manuscript amongst Newton’s papers by two famous historians of science in the middle of the twentieth century, everything changed. The manuscript, now known as De Gravitatione after its first line, illustrates the astonishing care with which Newton read the Principles, focusing his critical acumen on Descartes’s understanding of space, time, and motion. These criticisms of Descartes, in turn, shine light on otherwise opaque passages in Newton’s most significant published discussion of space, time, and motion, the Scholium in Principia mathematica. Indeed, the very title of the latter work represents both an homage to, and a swipe at, Descartes’s work: Newton would offer mathematical principles of natural philosophy to replace Descartes’s qualitative account. It is not a stretch to say that Newton saw further because he stood on Descartes’s shoulders, even if he wouldn’t admit it publicly.

Author(s):  
Joseph Mazur

This chapter focuses on the symbols created by Gottfried Leibniz. Alert to the advantages of proper symbols, Leibniz worked them, altered them, and tossed them whenever he felt the looming possibility that some poorly devised symbol might someday unnecessarily complicate mathematical exposition. He foresaw how symbols for polynomials could not possibly continue into algebra's generalizations at the turn of the seventeenth century. He knew how inconvenient symbols trapped the advancement of algebra in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries. By the last half of the seventeenth century, symbols were pervasive in mathematics manuscripts, largely due to Leibniz, along with others such as William Oughtred, René Descartes, and Isaac Newton. Among the more than 200 new symbols invented by Leibniz are his symbols for the differential and integral calculus.


2020 ◽  
Vol 7 (20) ◽  
pp. 08-17
Author(s):  
Lucicleia Chagas Magno ◽  
Miguel Chaquiam ◽  
Ruan Wenderson De Oliveira Sousa ◽  
Ruan Wenderson De Oliveira Sousa

Este trabalho tem como objetivo presentar vida e obra de Pappus de Alexandria, com destaque em seu teorema, e teve como base a seguinte questão de pesquisa: Qual a contribuição de Pappus de Alexandria à Matemática? Os caminhos foram percorridos tensdo como objetivo apresentar vida e obra de Pappus de Alexandria, com destaque em seu teorema. Neste sentido, a pesquisa, de cunho qualitativo, foi amparada em métodos bibliográficos, durante a qual foram revisados estudos de Chaquiam, (2017); Chaves (2013); Estrada, Sá et al (2000); Gillispie e Pereira (2007); Garnica e Souza (2012); Jones (s/d); Miguel e Miorim, (2002) e Roque (2012). Desse modo, com a execução dessa pesquisa foi possível observar que os trabalhos produzidos por Pappus de Alexandria, apresentam grandes contribuições à Matemática, em particular á Geometria, e também, a outras áreas de conhecimento, como na geografia, música, hidrostática, alquimia e na astronomia, além disso, sua principal obra, a Coletânea, e seu famoso teorema serviram como fonte de informação e inspiração para outros matemáticos, os quais contribuíram para a construção e aprimoramento de novos conhecimentos matemáticos, dentre eles, podemos citar René Descartes, Pierre de Fermat, Blaise Pascal, Isaac Newton e G. W Leibniz. Por conseguinte, percebeu-se que a História da Matemática é um ramo que estuda a evolução dos conteúdos matemáticos dentro do processo histórico-cultural, sendo um importante instrumento para o ensino de Matemática, principalmente, para a construção de conceitos, por isso torna-se essencial, também, o estudo e a utilização de biografias de personagens que contribuíram de alguma forma á Matemática, além de ser uma forma interessante de despertar o interesse dos estudantes pela Matemática e pela História da Matemática e, muito mais, fazer uso da história da matemática como recurso didático no processo de ensino e aprendizagem da matemática.


2015 ◽  
Vol 37 (4) ◽  
pp. 4202-1-4202-32
Author(s):  
Roberto de Andrade Martins ◽  
Cibelle Celestino Silva

Este artigo apresenta uma visão histórica geral sobre o desenvolvimento dos trabalhos de Isaac Newton a respeito da óptica, desde suas primeiras investigações em 1664 até o final de sua vida, quando publicou as várias edições de seu livro Opticks. Para permitir uma compreensão adequada do trabalho de Newton, são também apresentadas as contribuições de outros autores importantes do Século XVII, especialmente René Descartes, Walter Charleton, Robert Boyle, Robert Hooke e Christiaan Huygens. A análise dos trabalhos inéditos e publicados de Newton permite notar que ele jamais chegou a uma teoria definitiva a respeito da luz e das cores, adotando diversas hipóteses diferentes e mutuamente inconsistentes. O estudo aqui apresentado pode contribuir para complementar as visões simplificadas sobre a história da óptica e das contribuições de Newton sobre esse tema, bem como corrigir diversos equívocos presentes em obras didáticas e de divulgação científica sobre o assunto.


2019 ◽  
Vol 52 (1) ◽  
pp. 41-63 ◽  
Author(s):  
FABRIZIO BALDASSARRI

AbstractIn this article, I argue that the French philosopher René Descartes was far more involved in the study of plants than has been generally recognized. We know that he did not include a botanical section in his natural philosophy, and sometimes he differentiated between plants and living bodies. His position was, moreover, characterized by a methodological rejection of the catalogues of plants. However, this paper reveals a significant trend in Descartes's naturalistic pursuits, starting from the end of 1637, whereby he became increasingly interested in plants. I explore this shift by examining both Descartes's correspondence and several notes contained in theExcerpta anatomica. Grounded in direct observations, Descartes's work on vegetation provides a modest, though not unimportant, contribution to a natural-philosophical approach to the vegetal realm. This had a direct bearing on his lifelong ambition to explain the nature of living bodies and also fuelled the emergence of botany as a modern science.


2018 ◽  
Vol 6 (10) ◽  
pp. 9
Author(s):  
Luis Xavier López Farjeat

¿Qué es el color? Muchos físicos, químicos y filósofos han tratado de responder. Y posiblemente todos tengan algo de razón. Sin embargo, cada teoría, cada filosofía del color, arroja nuevas interrogantes y plantea dificultades. En este volumen hemos querido abordar el problema del color o de la percepción del color bajo la óptica de pensadores cuyas aportaciones en esta materia han sido poco exploradas: Teofrasto, René Descartes, Isaac Newton, Thomas Reid, Arthur Schopenhauer y algunos fenomenólogos del siglo xx, como Wilhelm Schapp o Adolf Reinach —por mencionar tan sólo dos de los muchos nombres que aparecen en el agudo análisis elaborado por Alejandro Vigo sobre filósofos pertenecientes a la tradición husserliana y post-husserliana.


2017 ◽  
Vol 21 (3) ◽  
pp. 87
Author(s):  
Francisco De Assis Gonçalves Junior ◽  
Thamires Cristine Corrêa

Este artigo visa discutir o contexto histórico e filosófico responsável pela origem do conceito que Edgar Morin define em sua obra A cabeça bem–feita: repensar a reforma, reformar o pensamento como, a "hiperspecialização" da análise científica, ou em outras palavras, a especialização que se fecha em si mesma, que fragmenta a realidade e que impede o pesquisador de conceber o global. Considerou-se como premissa que a origem desta segregação analítica advém das formas de pensamento oriundas da supervalorização da razão humana. Para análise desta conjectura foram considerados dois pensadores: René Descartes e Isaac Newton. Apresentaremos também algumas reflexões sobre a problemática da hiperespecialização científica na análise geográfica, principalmente no que tange a hiperespecialização organizada em torno da matemática/geometria, uma vez que a Geografia, devido a seu objeto de estudo (relação homem-sociedade/natureza), possui sua construção epistemológica pautada em questionamentos complexos e até mesmo subjetivos, ou seja, situações que demandam formas de análise multidimensionais, e que portanto, não apresentam coesão quando demasiadamente fragmentadas. Neste bojo, considera-se que a atuação de profissionais hiperespecializados (tanto licenciados como bacharéis) tem diluído a unidade da Geografia enquanto ciência voltada a uma compreensão ampla da realidade social. Palavras-chave: História da Ciência, hiperespecialização, epistemologia da Geografia


Metaphysics ◽  
2020 ◽  
pp. 26-38
Author(s):  
A. V Khodunov

This work consists of two parts. In the first part, a historical analysis is made with modern comments on the importance of a deep study of stable knowledge, experience and traditions of a geometric nature about the structure of the world accumulated by our civilization, which have passed thousands of years of testing. In addition to mathematics, in physics, the tradition of geometric research methods comes from Archimedes, through the work of Leonardo da Vinci, Galileo Galilei, René Descartes, Isaac Newton and other scientists. This trend is now stronger than ever. The second part briefly and summarizes the stages of how and what we have come to on this path.


Author(s):  
John A. Schuster

This article examines the physics of René Descartes. Descartes’ natural philosophy marks a significant moment in the larger history of physics. His system of natural philosophy was a novel, daring, and intricate construction in that field, with two main sets of historical significances for later physics. Before discussing these two significant consequences of Descartes’ natural philosophy for physics, the article provides an overview of the developmental anatomy of Cartesian physics during the period 1618–1644. In particular, it considers the successes, failures, and fate of Descartes’ early physico-mathematics programme, his work on physico-mathematical optics and corpuscular dynamics, and his career inflection between 1628 and 1633. It also explores Descartes’ ideas on vortex celestial mechanics, the explanatory style of mature Cartesian physics, and his work on classical mechanics. Finally, it looks at Descartes’ concerns with realist Copernicanism.


2021 ◽  
pp. 76-94
Author(s):  
Fabrizio Baldassarri

In René Descartes' works there are four major references to living bodies as objects of his natural philosophy. The first is contained in the Fifth part of the Discours de la Méthode, published in June 1637, where Descartes provides a mechanical explanation of the heartbeat and other living functions of the body. The second is in a bio-medical note collected in the Excerpta anatomica dated November 1637, where he discusses nutrition and growth. The third is the famous claim on the absence of a section on living bodies in the Principia philosophiae, published in 1644. The fourth is in La Description du corps humain, Descartes' late physiology likely dated 1647-1648. In this article, by exploring these passages and contextualizing his physiological observations of animals and plants, I reassemble Descartes' science of life: his dismissal of soul, his mechanical framework, his interpretation of bodily self-maintenance and growth, his understanding of living bodies as integrated and organic systems, and the role of a power such as the immutatio and forces such as the impetus.


Author(s):  
Peter Pesic

René Descartes began his career writing about music, which affected his innovative natural philosophy throughout its development. His first book was about music, addressed to another natural philosopher interested in it, Isaac Beeckman. In this book, Descartes used music as an exemplar of the approach he would take to mathematics and physics. This book remained important in Descartes’s correspondence with Marin Mersenne, which included musical as well as scientific topics. This chapter reads this lengthy correspondence as showing the interaction between musical, mathematical, and philosophical themes in Descartes’s work. Musical observations led to Descartes’s initial observations of the overtones of vibrating strings, which in turn led to wider consideration of mechanics, motion in a vacuum, and eventually to his continuum theory of the universe. This chapter argues that Descartes’s rejection of the vacuum came in the context of musical-physical problems. Descartes’s theories emerged in constant dialogue with musical issues and problems. Throughout the book where various sound examples are referenced, please see http://mitpress.mit.edu/musicandmodernscience (please note that the sound examples should be viewed in Chrome or Safari Web browsers).


Sign in / Sign up

Export Citation Format

Share Document